•  594
    Properties and Powers
    Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1 223-254. 2004.
  •  547
    Mental Causation
    with David Robb
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Worries about mental causation are prominent in contemporary discussions of the mind and human agency. Originally, the problem of mental causation was that of understanding how a mental substance (thought to be immaterial) could interact with a material substance, a body. Most philosophers nowadays repudiate immaterial minds, but the problem of mental causation has not gone away. Instead, focus has shifted to mental properties. How could mental properties be causally relevant to bodily behavior?…Read more
  •  442
    The ontological turn
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (1). 1999.
  •  390
    Levels of reality
    Ratio 16 (3). 2003.
    Philosophers and non-philosophers have been attracted to the idea that the world incorporates levels of being: higher-level items – ordinary objects, artifacts, human beings – depend on, but are not in any sense reducible to, items at lower levels. I argue that the motivation for levels stems from an implicit acceptance of a Picture Theory of language according to which we can ‘read off’ features of the world from ways we describe the world. Abandonment of the Picture Theory opens the way to a ‘…Read more
  •  367
    Privileged access
    Mind 97 (386): 238-51. 1988.
  •  342
    Dispositions
    Synthese 144 (3): 343-356. 2005.
    Appeals to dispositionality in explanations of phenomena in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, require that we first agree on what we are talking about. I sketch an account of what dispositionality might be. That account will place me at odds with most current conceptions of dispositionality. My aim is not to establish a weighty ontological thesis, however, but to move the discussion ahead in two respects. First, I want to call attention to the extent to which assumptions philosophers have …Read more
  •  276
    This comprehensive textbook, written by a leading author in the field, provides a survey of mainstream conceptions of the nature of mind accessible to readers with little or no background in philosophy. Included are the dualist, behaviourist, and functionalist accounts of the nature of mind, along with a critical assessment of recent trends in the subject. The problem of consciousness, widely thought to be the chief roadblock to our understanding of the mind, is addressed throughout the book and…Read more
  •  220
    From an ontological point of view
    Oxford University Press. 2003.
    From an Ontological Point of View is a highly original and accessible exploration of fundamental questions about what there is. John Heil discusses such issues as whether the world includes levels of reality; the nature of objects and properties; the demands of realism; what makes things true; qualities, powers, and the relation these bear to one another. He advances an account of the fundamental constituents of the world around us, and applies this account to problems that have plagued recent w…Read more
  •  201
    Mental Causation (edited book)
    Clarendon Press. 1993.
    Common sense and philosophical tradition agree that mind makes a difference. What we do depends not only on how our bodies are put together, but also on what we think. Explaining how mind can make a difference has proved challenging, however. Some have urged that the project faces an insurmountable dilemma: either we concede that mentalistic explanations of behavior have only a pragmatic standing or we abandon our conception of the physical domain as causally autonomous. Although each option has…Read more
  •  198
    Hylomorphism: what’s not to like?
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 11): 2657-2670. 2018.
    The paper comprises an attempt on the part of the author to understand what hylomorphism is, both in its original Aristotelian guise, and in recent work by philosophers who defend what they call hylomorphism. Two species or strands of hylomorphism are identified and discussed. Universals, essences, and substantial and accidental forms make cameo appearances, and the implications of an Aristotelian ontology of stuffs are explored.
  •  195
    Truthmaking and fundamentality
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 3): 849-860. 2016.
    Consider the idea that some entities are more fundamental than others, some entities ‘ground’ other, less fundamental, entities. What is it for something to be more fundamental than another, or for something to ‘ground’ something else? This paper urges the rejection of conceptions of grounding and fundamentality according to which reality has a hierarchical structure in which higher-level entities are taken to be distinct from but metaphysically dependent on more fundamental lower-level entities…Read more
  •  189
    Powers and the Realization Relation
    The Monist 94 (1): 34-53. 2011.
  •  187
    The legacy of linguisticism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2). 2006.
    In recent work on truth and truthmaking, D. M. Armstrong has defended a version of 'truthmaker necessitarianism', the doctrine that truths necessitate truthmakers. Truthmaker necessitarianism, he contends, requires the postulation of 'totality facts', which serve as ingredients of truthmakers for general truths and negative truths, and propositions, which function as the fundamental truth bearers. I argue that neither totality facts nor propositions need figure in an account of truthmaking, and …Read more
  •  156
    Believing what one ought
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (11): 752-765. 1983.
  •  155
    Doxastic agency
    Philosophical Studies 43 (3). 1983.
  •  139
    Mental causes
    with Alfred Mele
    American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1): 61-71. 1991.
    Our suspicion is that philosophers who tie the fate of agency to advances in cognitive science simultaneously underestimate that conception's tenacity and overestimate their ability to divine the course of empirical inquiry. For the present, however, we shall pretend that current ideas about what would be required for the scientific vindication of folk psychology are apt, and ask where this leaves the notion of agency. Our answer will be that it leaves that notion on the whole unaffected.
  •  128
    Kinds and essences
    Ratio 18 (4). 2005.
    Brian Ellis advances a robust species of realism he calls Physical Realism. Physical Realism includes an ontology comprising three kinds of universal and three kinds of particular: a six‐category ontology. After comparing Physical Realism to a modest two‐category ontology inspired by Locke, I mention two apparent difficulties a proponent of a six‐category ontology might address.1.
  •  118
    Speechless brutes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (3): 400-406. 1982.
  •  112
    Supervenience deconstructed
    European Journal of Philosophy 6 (2): 146-155. 1998.
  •  104
    Accidents, Modes, Tropes, and Universals
    American Philosophical Quarterly 51 (4): 333-344. 2014.
    What are properties? Examples are easy. Consider a particular billiard ball. The ball is red, spherical, and has a definite mass. The ball's redness, sphericity, and mass are properties: properties of the ball. Putting it this way invites a distinction between the ball, a bearer of properties, and the ball's properties. Some philosophers deny that there are properties. To say that the ball is red or spherical, for instance, is just to say that the predicates "is red" and "is spherical" apply tru…Read more
  •  104
    The Universe as We Find It
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    What does reality encompass? Is it exclusively physical, or does it include mental and 'abstract' aspects? What are the elements of being, reality's raw materials? John Heil offers stimulating answers to these questions framed in terms of a comprehensive metaphysics of substances and properties inspired by Descartes, Locke, and their successors.
  •  100
    Multiple realizability
    American Philosophical Quarterly 36 (3): 189-208. 1999.
  •  100
    III—Aristotelian Supervenience
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 115 (1pt1): 41-56. 2015.
    Three matchsticks could be arranged on a table so as to form a triangle. Were you to place a lump of sugar into a cup of hot tea it would dissolve. You might never have been born. Such assertions express modal judgements and, as we suppose, truths about the universe. But if modal judgements can be true, what features of the universe make them true? Thanks largely to the efforts of David Lewis, philosophers nowadays find it natural to appeal to alternative worlds to explicate modality. Something …Read more
  •  96
    Doxastic incontinence
    Mind 93 (369): 56-70. 1984.
  •  96
    Are We Brains in a Vat? Top Philosopher Says No
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 427-436. 1987.
    In Reason, Truth, and History, Hilary Putnam addresses the notion that we might all be brains in a vat in a way that has been widely discussed.1 What follows is an attempt to get dear on Putnam's argument, more particularly, to determine how exactly that argument goes and what precisely it is supposed to establish. Putnam's presentation is not unambiguous on either count, nor is it always as dear as one might have wished.