• Indeterminism and Agency
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    Develops the formal theory of action, or agency, that forms the background of the book. The account is cast against the background of Prior's theory of branching, or indeterministic, time. Against this background, the chapter develops precise notions of action and ability for both individuals and groups.
  • Group Oughts
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The notion of what an agent ought to do is generalized to yield a notion of what groups of agents ought to do. Relations among the obligations governing groups and subgroups are explored, as well as the connections among different species of individual act utilitarianism, group act utilitarianism, and rule utilitarianism.
  • Ought to Be
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    Supplements the background theory of indeterministic time with a standard deontic logic, representing what ought to be the case. Taken together with the formal notion of action introduced in the previous chapter, the framework now allows us to speak about what it ought to be that the agent does, and to explore the possibility that this notion should be identified with the notion of what the agent ought to do. Examples are developed to show that the two notions should not be identified.
  • Ought to Do
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    An analogy is developed between action in an indeterministic setting and choice under uncertainty, as it is studied in decision theory. Various dominance relations among actions are explored, and used both to provide a semantic account of what agents ought to do and to formulate a notion of dominance act utilitarianism. The ideas are related to problems involving independence, conditionals, and sure‐thing reasoning.
  • Conditional Oughts
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The notion of what an agent ought to do is refined to yield a notion conditional obligation, representing what the agent ought to do under various circumstances. Patterns of reasoning in the conditional deontic logic are explored. In contrast to the dominance account developed earlier, a competing notion of orthodox act utilitarianism is formulated.
  • Strategic Oughts
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The notion of what an agent ought to do at a moment is generalized to yield a notion of what the agent ought to do over extended periods of time. This requires us to develop the notion of a strategy as a function from moments to actions available at those moments and appropriate notions of strategic dominance. A strategic ought operator is introduced and used to analyze the debate between actualists and possibilists concerning the ways in which an agent's obligations depend on his or her future …Read more
  • Chapter 1 Overview
    In John Horty (ed.), Agency and deontic logic, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  • Unlike statutory law, which relies on the explicit formulation of rules, common law is thought to emerge from a complex doctrine of precedential constraint, according to which decisions in earlier cases constrain later courts while still allowing these courts the freedom to address new situations in creative ways. Although this doctrine is applied by legal practitioners on a daily basis, it has proved to be considerably more difficult to develop an adequate theoretical account of the doctrine it…Read more
  •  10
    Nonmonotonic Logic
    In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell. 2017.
    The goal of a logic is to define a consequence relation between a set of formulas Γ and, in most cases, an individual formula A. This definition generally takes one of two forms. From a proof theoretic standpoint, A is said to be a consequence of Γ whenever there is a deduction of A from the set Γ, viewed as a set of premises; from a model theoretic standpoint, A is said to be a consequence of Γ whenever A holds in every model that satisfies each formula in Γ.
  •  41
    Introduction
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (6): 593-594. 2015.
  •  40
    Action types in stit semantics
    Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4): 617-637. 2017.
  • Handbook of Deontic Logic and Normative System, Volume 2 (edited book)
    with Dov Gabbay, ,, Xavier Parent, Ron van der Meyden, and Leon van der Torre
    College Publications. forthcoming.
  •  12
    Skepticism and floating conclusions
    Artificial Intelligence 135 (1-2): 55-72. 2002.
  •  22
    Modifying the reason model
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 29 (2): 271-285. 2020.
    In previous work, I showed how the “reason model” of precedential constraint could naturally be generalized from the standard setting in which it was first developed to a richer setting in which dimensional information is represented as well. Surprisingly, it then turned out that, in this new dimensional setting, the reason model of constraint collapsed into the “result model,” which supports only a fortiori reasoning. The purpose of this note is to suggest a modification of the reason model of …Read more
  • The Handbook of Deontic Logic (Vol. II) (edited book)
    with Dov Gabbay, Ron van der Meyden, Xavier Parent, and Leandert van der Torre
    College Publications. forthcoming.
  •  105
    Agency and deontic logic
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    John Horty effectively develops deontic logic (the logic of ethical concepts like obligation and permission) against the background of a formal theory of agency. He incorporates certain elements of decision theory to set out a new deontic account of what agents ought to do under various conditions over extended periods of time. Offering a conceptual rather than technical emphasis, Horty's framework allows a number of recent issues from moral theory to be set out clearly and discussed from a unif…Read more
  •  41
    Epistemic Oughts in Stit Semantics
    Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 6. 2019.
  •  39
    Reasoning with dimensions and magnitudes
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 27 (3): 309-345. 2019.
    This paper shows how two models of precedential constraint can be broadened to include legal information represented through dimensions. I begin by describing a standard representation of legal cases based on boolean factors alone, and then reviewing two models of constraint developed within this standard setting. The first is the “result model”, supporting only a fortiori reasoning. The second is the “reason model”, supporting a richer notion of constraint, since it allows the reasons behind a …Read more
  •  10
    Reasons as Defaults
    Oxford University Press USA. 2012.
    Although the study of reasons plays an important role in both epistemology and moral philosophy, little attention has been devoted to the question of how, exactly, reasons interact to support the actions or conclusions they do. In this book, John F. Horty attempts to answer this question by providing a precise, concrete account of reasons and their interaction, based on the logic of default reasoning. The book begins with an intuitive, accessible introduction to default logic itself, and then ar…Read more
  • Some Aspects of Meaning in Non-Contingent Language
    Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh. 1986.
    Frege's writings on meaning are often interpreted within the framework of possible worlds semantics. The resulting theories rely on contingency to account for a variety of linguistic phenomena, such as the behavior of expressions in propositional attitude contexts, or the idea that a definition might fix the reference of an expression without establishing its meaning. In this thesis, I interpret Frege's ideas within a different framework, to provide a semantic theory that is able to account for …Read more
  •  82
    Evaluating new options in the context of existing plans
    with Martha E. Pollack
    Artificial Intelligence 127 (2): 199-220
    This paper contributes to the foundations of a theory of rational choice for artificial agents in dynamic environments. Our work is developed within a theoretical framework, originally due to Bratman, that models resource-bounded agents as operating against the background of some current set of intentions, which helps to frame their subsequent reasoning. In contrast to the standard theory of rational choice, where options are evaluated in isolation, we therefore provide an analysis of situations …Read more
  •  62
    A sceptical theory of inheritance in nonmonotonic semantic networks
    with Richmond H. Thomason and David S. Touretzky
    Artificial Intelligence 42 (2-3): 311-348. 1990.
    inheritance reasoning in semantic networks allowing for multiple inheritance with exceptions. The approach leads to a definition of iaheritance that is..
  •  73
    The book begins by focusing on the psychological constraints governing Frege's notion of sense, or meaning, and argues that, given these constraints, even the ...
  •  83
    This paper works within a particular framework for reasoning about actions—sometimes known as the framework of “stit semantics”—originally due to Belnap and Perloff, based ultimately on the theory of indeterminism set out in Prior’s indeterministic tense logic, and developed in full detail by Belnap, Perloff, and Xu [3]. The issues I want to consider arise when certain normative, or decision theoretic, notions are introduced into this framework: here I will focus on the notion of a right action,…Read more
  •  37
    Constraint and Freedom in the Common Law
    Philosophers' Imprint 15 1-27. 2015.
    This paper contributes to our formal understanding of the common law — especially the nature of the reasoning involved, but also its point, or justification, in terms of social coordination. I present two apparently distinct models of constraint by precedent in the common law, establish their equivalence, and argue for a perspective according to which courts are best thought of, not as creating and modifying rules, but as generating a social priority ordering on reasons through a procedure that …Read more
  •  61
    The purpose of this paper is to question some commonly accepted patterns of reasoning involving nonmonotonic logics that generate multiple extensions. In particular, I argue that the phenomenon of floating conclusions indicates a problem with the view that the skeptical consequences of such theories should be identified with the statements that are supported by each of their various extensions.
  •  41
    Right actions in perspective
    In Henrik Lagerlund, Sten Lindström & Rysiek Sliwinski (eds.), Modality Matters: Twenty-Five Essays in Honour of Krister Segerberg, Uppsala Philosophical Studies 53. pp. 53. 2006.
  •  12
    In this short monograph, John Horty explores the difficulties presented for Gottlob Frege's semantic theory, as well as its modern descendents, by the treatment of defined expressions. The book begins by focusing on the psychological constraints governing Frege's notion of sense, or meaning, and argues that, given these constraints, even the treatment of simple stipulative definitions led Frege to important difficulties. Horty is able to suggest ways out of these difficulties that are both philo…Read more
  •  102
    Argument construction and reinstatement in logics for defeasible reasoning
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 9 (1): 1-28. 2001.
    This paper points out some problems with two recent logical systems – one due to Prakken and Sartor, the other due to Kowalski and Toni – designedfor the representation of defeasible arguments in general, but with a specialemphasis on legal reasoning.
  •  355
    The Logic of Reasons
    with Shyam Nair
    In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, Oxford University Press. pp. 67-84. 2018.
    In this chapter, we begin by sketching in the broadest possible strokes the ideas behind two formal systems that have been introduced with to goal of explicating the ways in which reasons interact to support the actions and conclusions they do. The first of these is the theory of defeasible reasoning developed in the seminal work of Pollock; the second is a more recent theory due to Horty, which adapts and develops the default logic introduced by Reiter to provide an account of reasons. However…Read more