•  11
    Book reviews (review)
    Philosophia 23 (1-4): 345-415. 1994.
  •  1042
    Does Psychological Egoism Entail Ethical Egoism?
    Review of Metaphysics 76 (1): 115-133. 2022.
    [If you find this article interesting, let me mention another of my articles, “On Deducing Ethical Egoism from Psychological Egoism” (Theoria, 2023), which in many ways is a more thorough treatment of the topic. But it’s not an expanded version of this one. For instance, each article addresses arguments not addressed in the other.] Philosophers generally reject the view that psychological egoism (suitably supplemented with further premises) entails ethical egoism. Their rejections are generally …Read more
  •  577
    A familiar question is whether psychological egoism (suitably supplemented with plausible further premises) entails ethical egoism. This paper considers this question, treating it much more thoroughly than do any previous treatments. For instance, it discusses all of the most common understandings of ethical and psychological egoism. It further discusses many strategies and arguments relevant to the question addressed. Although this procedure creates complexity, it has value. It forestalls the s…Read more
  •  1044
    Two kinds of moral relativism
    Journal of Value Inquiry 29 (2): 187-192. 1995.
    Discussions of moral relativism commonly distinguish between normative relativism (NR) and moral judgment relativism (MJR) without highlighting the differences between the two. One significant difference—a difference between normative relativism and the most prevalent type of moral judgment relativism—is not immediately obvious and has not been discussed in print. This paper explains it and draws out some of its philosophical consequences.
  •  384
    On an Alleged Refutation of Ethical Egoism
    Journal of Value Inquiry 57 (3). 2023.
    In his 1972 paper “A Short Refutation Ethical Egoism,” Richmond Campbell purports to refute ethical egoism via a simple reductio. Although his argument has received critical attention, it has not been satisfactorily answered. In this paper I answer it, for reasons that go well beyond my immediate topic. Campbell’s argument calls for an answer partly because, as I show, if it succeeds against ethical egoism, then variations of it refute many other normative ethical theories, such as act utilitari…Read more
  •  75
  •  388
    A familiar claim, meant as a challenge to moral knowledge, is that we can credibly accept putative moral facts just in case they explain natural facts. This paper critically addresses Elizabeth Tropman’s response to a version of that claim. Her response has interest partly because it falls within, and extends, an influential philosophical tradition – that of trying to expose (some) skeptical challenges as spurious or ill-conceived. Also, Tropman’s target is not just any version of the claim just…Read more
  •  19
    Two (Faulty) Responses to the Challenge of Amoralism
    The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 44 248-253. 1998.
    To the question "Why should I be moral?" there is a simple answer that some philosophers find tempting. There is also a response, common enough to be dubbed the standard response, to the simple answer. In what follows, I show that the SA and SR are unsatisfactory; they share a serious defect.
  • 'Humean' Rationality, Morality, and Reasons for Action
    Dissertation, The University of Wisconsin - Madison. 1988.
    This thesis clarifies and defends the view of practical reason often dubbed "Humean", "instrumental", or "preference-based". Three familiar charges against this view are addressed, and claimed to be ineffective. They are: first, that the Humean view entails the easily refuted theory that all reasons for action have their source in individual desires; second, that it brings with it an extreme version of ethical relativism; and third, that it presupposes a view of motivation which has been shown t…Read more
  •  808
    Among the most animating debates in eighteenth-century British ethics was the debate over psychological egoism, the view that our most basic desires are self-interested. An important episode in that debate, less well known than it should be, was the exchange between Francis Hutcheson and John Clarke of Hull. In the early editions of his Inquiry into Virtue, Hutcheson argued ingeniously against psychological egoism; in his Foundation of Morality, Clarke argued ingeniously against Hutcheson’s argu…Read more
  •  1575
    Butler's Stone
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (4). 2018.
    Early in the eleventh of his Fifteen Sermons, Joseph Butler advances his best-known argument against psychological hedonism. Elliott Sober calls that argument Butler’s stone, and famously objects to it. I consider whether Butler’s stone has philosophical value. In doing so I examine, and reject, two possible ways of overcoming Sober’s objection, each of which has proponents. In examining the first way I discuss Lord Kames’s version of the stone argument, which has hitherto escaped scholarly atte…Read more
  •  550
    Francis Hutcheson and John Clarke: Self-Interest, Desire, and Divine Impassibility
    International Philosophical Quarterly 57 (3): 315-330. 2017.
    In this article I address a puzzle about one of Francis Hutcheson’s objections to psychological egoism. The puzzle concerns his premise that God receives no benefit from rewarding the virtuous. Why, in the early editions of his Inquiry Concerning Virtue (1725, 1726), does Hutcheson leave this premise undefended? And why, in the later editions (1729, 1738), does he continue to do so, knowing that in 1726 John Clarke of Hull had subjected the premise to plausible criticism, geared to the very audi…Read more
  •  36469
    Cultural Relativism
    Human Rights Quarterly 22 (2). 2000.
    In this paper I refute the chief arguments for cultural relativism, meaning the moral (not the descriptive) theory that goes by that name. In doing this I walk some oft-trodden paths, but I also break new ones. For instance, I take unusual pains to produce an adequate formulation of cultural relativism, and I distinguish that thesis from the relativism of present-day anthropologists, with which it is often conflated. In addition, I address not one or two, but eleven arguments for cultural relat…Read more
  •  5245
    Hedonism
    In Ruth Chadwick (ed.), Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, 2nd ed., vol. 2, Academic Press. pp. 566-73. 2012.
    This article covers four types of hedonism: ancient hedonism; ethical hedonism; axiological hedonism; and psychological hedonism. It concentrates on the latter two types, both by clarifying them and by discussing arguments in their behalf. It closes with a few words about the relevance of those positions to applied ethics.
  •  1
    Troubles for Psychological Hedonism
    Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research 10. 1999.
  •  650
    Motivation and practical reasons
    Erkenntnis 47 (1): 105-127. 1997.
    In discussions of practical reason we often encounter the view that a fact is a reason for an agent to act only if the fact is capable of moving the agent to act. This view figures centrally in many philosophical controversies, and while taken for granted by some, it is vigorously disputed by others. In this essay I show that if the disputed position is correctly interpreted, it is well armored against stock objections and implied by a premise that is not only plausible, but generally accepted b…Read more
  •  1213
    Dismissive Replies to "Why Should I Be Moral?"
    Social Theory and Practice 35 (3): 341-368. 2009.
    The question "Why should I be moral?," taken as a request for reasons to be moral, strikes many philosophers as silly, confused, or otherwise out of line. Hence we find many attempts to dismiss it as spurious. This paper addresses four such attempts and shows that they fail. It does so partly by discussing various errors about reasons for action, errors that lie at the root of the view that "Why should I be moral?" is ill-conceived. Such errors include the mistake of confusing different uses of …Read more
  •  50
    Altruism and the prisoner's dilemma
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (3). 1991.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  83
    Prisoner's dilemma from a moral point of view
    Theory and Decision 41 (2): 187-193. 1996.
    In a recent issue of this journal, C. L. Sheng claims to havesolved andexplained the Prisoner's Dilemma (PD) by studying it ‘from a moral point of view’ - i.e., by assuming that each player feels sympathy for the other. Sheng does not fully clarify this claim, but there is textual evidence that his point is this: PD's arise only for agents who feel little or no sympathy for each other; they cannot arise in the presence of a high degree of reciprocal sympathy. A high degree of such sympathysolves…Read more
  •  1976
    John Clarke of Hull's Argument for Psychological Egoism
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (1): 69-89. 2015.
    John Clarke of Hull, one of the eighteenth century's staunchest proponents of psychological egoism, defended that theory in his Foundation of Morality in Theory and Practice. He did so mainly by opposing the objections to egoism in the first two editions of Francis Hutcheson's Inquiry into Virtue. But Clarke also produced a challenging, direct argument for egoism which, regrettably, has received virtually no scholarly attention. In this paper I give it some of the attention it merits. In additio…Read more
  •  496
    Cultural Relativism and Tolerance
    Lyceum 6 (1): 1-11. 1994.
    This was a class handout that I turned into a publication. As its title indicates, it's about the relation (or non-relation) of (ethical) cultural relativism to tolerance. Core elements of the paper were later absorbed into sections 5K, 6M, and 7K of my paper "Cultural Relativism" (2000), which is listed (and downloadable) on my PhilPapers page.
  •  109
    Moral Freedom (review)
    Philosophia 23 (1-4): 407-408. 1994.
  •  4020
    The Problem for Normative Cultural Relativism
    Ratio Juris 11 (3): 272-290. 1998.
    The key problem for normative (or moral) cultural relativism arises as soon as we try to formulate it. It resists formulations that are (1) clear, precise, and intelligible; (2) plausible enough to warrant serious attention; and (3) faithful to the aims of leading cultural relativists, one such aim being to produce an important alternative to moral universalism. Meeting one or two of these conditions is easy; meeting all three is not. I discuss twenty-four candidates for the label "cultural rela…Read more
  •  946
    Exciting Reasons and Moral Rationalism in Hutcheson's Illustrations upon the Moral Sense
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 50 (1): 53-83. 2012.
    One of the most oft-cited parts of Francis Hutcheson’s Illustrations upon the Moral Sense (1728) is his discussion of “exciting reasons.” In this paper I address the question: What is the function of that discussion? In particular, what is its relation to Hutcheson’s attempt to show that the rationalists’ normative thesis ultimately implies, contrary to their moral epistemology, that moral ideas spring from a sense? Despite first appearances, Hutcheson’s discussion of exciting reasons is not par…Read more
  •  800
    The Prisoner's Dilemma (PD) exhibits a tragedy in this sense: if the players are fully informed and rational, they are condemned to a jointly dispreferred outcome. In this essay I address the following question: What feature of the PD's payoff structure is necessary and sufficient to produce the tragedy? In answering it I use the notion of a trembling-hand equilibrium. In the final section I discuss an implication of my argument, an implication which bears on the persistence of the problem posed…Read more
  •  1101
    In a well-known footnote in Book 3 of his Treatise of Human Nature, Hume calls William Wollaston's moral theory a "whimsical system" and purports to destroy it with a few brief objections. The first of those objections, although fatally flawed, has hitherto gone unrefuted. To my knowledge, its chief error has escaped attention. In this paper I expose that error; I also show that it has relevance beyond the present subject. It can occur with regard to any moral theory which, like Wollaston's, loc…Read more
  •  846
    Justifying reasons, motivating reasons, and agent relativism in ethics
    Philosophical Studies 118 (3): 373-399. 2004.
    According to agent relativism, each person's moral requirements are relative to her desires or interests. That is, whether a person morally ought to ø depends on what interests or desires she has. Some philosophers charge that the main argument for agent relativism trades on an ambiguity in the term "reason," "reason for action,'' or the like. This paper shows that although the argument for agent relativism may indeed harbor an ambiguity, the ambiguity is no Achilles’ heel. To remove it is not t…Read more
  •  17
    Desires and Practical Reasons
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 9 123-128. 2006.
    This paper refutes a common and influential thesis about the conditions under which desires provide agents with practical reasons. That thesis is that if any agent. A, has a desire which A could satisfy by (ping, then A has a reason—a minimal reason, at least—to (p. Although this thesis comes close to stating a truth, it falls short.