•  27
    Positing a Space Mirror Mechanism Intentional Understanding Without Action?
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (5-6): 5-6. 2013.
    Recent evidence regarding a novel functionality of the mirror neuron system , a so-called 'space mirror mechanism', seems to reinforce the central role of the MNS in social cognition. According to the space mirror hypothesis, neural mirroring accounts for understanding not just what an observed agent is doing, but also the range of potential actions that a suitably located object affords an observed agent in the absence of any motor behaviour. This paper aims to show that the advocate of this sp…Read more
  •  345
    Responsibility for implicitly biased behavior: A habit‐based approach
    Journal of Social Philosophy 53 (2): 239-254. 2021.
    This paper has a two-fold goal. First, I defend the view that the prejudicial behaviour that results from implicit biases is best understood as a type of habitual action—as a harmful, yet deeply entrenched, passively acquired, socially relevant type of habit. Second, I explore how characterizing such implicitly biased behaviour as a habit aids our understanding of the responsibility we bear for it. As habits are ultimately susceptible of being controlled, agents ought to be held responsible for …Read more
  •  702
    Accessibility, implicit bias, and epistemic justification
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 7): 1529-1547. 2018.
    It has recently been argued that beliefs formed on the basis of implicit biases pose a challenge for accessibilism, since implicit biases are consciously inaccessible, yet they seem to be relevant to epistemic justification. Recent empirical evidence suggests, however, that while we may typically lack conscious access to the source of implicit attitudes and their impact on our beliefs and behaviour, we do have access to their content. In this paper, I discuss the notion of accessibility required…Read more
  •  194
    Implicit Bias: From Social Structure to Representational Format
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 33 (1): 41-60. 2018.
    In this paper, I argue against the view that the representational structure of the implicit attitudes responsible for implicitly biased behaviour is propositional—as opposed to associationist. The proposal under criticism moves from the claim that implicit biased behaviour can occasionally be modulated by logical and evidential considerations to the view that the structure of the implicit attitudes responsible for such biased behaviour is propositional. I argue, in particular, against the truth …Read more
  •  23
    Mind and Supermind
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226): 139-142. 2007.
    This is a review of Mind and Supermind. By KEITH FRANKISH. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp xiv + 255. Price £45.00 (US $75.00). ISBN 0521 812038 (hardback).
  •  224
    Michael Dummett (1925-2011)
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 31 (1): 163-169. 2012.
    Michael Dummett's Obituary
  •  17
    Opacity, Know-How States, and their Content
    Disputatio 7 (40): 61-83. 2015.
    The main goal of this paper is to defend the thesis that the content of know-how states is an accuracy assessable type of nonconceptual content. My argument proceeds in two stages. I argue, first, that the intellectualist distinction between types of ways of grasping the same kind of content is uninformative unless it is tied in with a distinction between kinds of contents. Second, I consider and reject the objection that, if the content of know-how states is non-conceptual, it will be mysteriou…Read more
  •  318
    Implicit Bias: from social structure to representational format
    Theoria : An International Journal for Theory, History and Fundations of Science 33 (1): 41-60. 2018.
    In this paper, I argue against the view that the representational structure of the implicit attitudes responsible for implicitly biased behaviour is propositional—as opposed to associationist. The proposal under criticism moves from the claim that implicit biased behaviour can occasionally be modulated by logical and evidential considerations to the view that the structure of the implicit attitudes responsible for such biased behaviour is propositional. I argue, in particular, against the truth …Read more
  •  352
    Is action-guiding vision cognitively penetrable? More specifically, is the visual processing that guides our goal-directed actions sensitive to semantic information from cognitive states? This paper critically examines a recent family of arguments whose aim is to challenge a widespread and influential view in philosophy and cognitive science: the view that action-guiding vision is cognitively impenetrable. I argue, in response, that while there may very well be top–down causal influences on acti…Read more
  • Perceptual experience and its contents
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 23 (4): 375-392. 2002.
  •  14
    The Implicit Conception of Implicit Conceptions
    Philosophical Issues 9 115-120. 1998.
    Peacocke's characterization of what he calls implicit conceptions recognizes the significance of a subset of contentful states in making rational behavior intelligible. What Peacocke has to offer in this paper is an account of (i) why we need implicit conceptions; (ii) how we can discover them; (iii) what they explain; (iv) what they are; and (v) how they can help us to better understand some issues in the theory of meaning and the theory of knowledge. The rationalist tradition in which Peacocke…Read more
  •  172
    Meaning, dispositions, and normativity
    Minds and Machines 9 (3): 399-413. 1999.
    In a recent paper, Paul Coates defends a sophisticated dispositional account which allegedly resolves the sceptical paradox developed by Kripke in his monograph on Wittgenstein's treatment of following a rule (Kripke, 1982). Coates' account appeals to a notion of 'homeostasis', unpacked as a subject's second-order disposition to maintain a consistent pattern of extended first-order dispositions regarding her linguistic behavior. This kind of account, Coates contends, provides a naturalistic mode…Read more
  •  102
    Ecological content
    Pragmatics and Cognition 5 (2): 253-281. 1997.
    The paper has a negative and a positive side. The negative side argues that the classical notions of narrow and wide content are not suitable for the purposes of psychological explanation. The positive side shows how to characterize an alternative notion of content that is suitable for those purposes. This account is supported by a way of conceptualizing computation that is constitutively dependent upon properties external to the system and empirical research in developmental psychology. My main…Read more
  •  58
    Social Vision: Breaking a Philosophical Impasse?
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4): 611-615. 2015.
    I argue that findings in support of Adams and Kveraga’s functional forecast model of emotion expression processing help settle the debate between rich and sparse views of the content of perceptual experience. In particular, I argue that these results in social vision suggest that the distinctive phenomenal character of experiences involving high-level properties such as emotions and social traits is best explained by their being visually experienced as opposed to being brought about by perceptua…Read more
  •  140
    What We Do When We Judge
    Dialectica 65 (3): 345-367. 2011.
    In this paper I argue on two fronts. First, I press for the view that judging is a type of mental action, as opposed to those who think that judging is involuntary and hence not an action. Second, I argue that judging is specifically a type of non-voluntary mental action. My account of the non-voluntary nature of the mental act of judging differs, however, from standard non-voluntarist views, according to which ‘non-voluntary’ just means regulated by epistemic reasons. In addition, judging is no…Read more
  •  5
    Review of Language in the World. A Philosophical Enquiry. Max J. Cresswell (review)
    with Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Richard Wyatt, William S. Robinson, Matthew Elton, Austen Clark, Berent Enç, and James L. Pate
    Philosophical Psychology 9 (1): 111-140. 1996.
    Left brain‐right brain differences: inquiries, evidence, and new approaches, James F. Iaccino. Hillsdale, NH: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1993. ISBN 0–8058–1340–3Artificial intelligence: a philosophical introduction, Jack Copeland Oxford: Blackwell, 1993 ISBN 0–631–18384–1Shadows of the mind, Roger Penrose. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. ISBN 019–8539789Raw feeling: a philosophical account of the essence of consciousness, R. Kirk. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994. ISBN 0–19–824081–3Vision:…Read more
  •  193
    Nonconceptual content
    Philosophy Compass 2 (3). 2007.
    Nonconceptualists maintain that there are ways of representing the world that do not reflect the concepts a creature possesses. They claim that the content of these representational states is genuine content because it is subject to correctness conditions, but it is nonconceptual because the creature to which we attribute it need not possess any of the concepts involved in the specification of that content. Appeals to nonconceptual content have seemed especially useful in attempts to capture the…Read more
  •  110
    Implicit conception of implicit conceptions
    Philosophical Issues 9 115-120. 1998.
    A commentary on Peacocke's notion of implicit conceptions.
  •  75
    Compositionality, iconicity, and perceptual nonconceptualism
    Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 177-193. 2011.
    This paper concerns the role of the structural properties of representations in determining the nature of their content. I take as a starting point Fodor's (2007) and Heck's (2007) recent arguments making the iconic structure of perceptual representations essential in establishing their content as content of a different (nonconceptual) kind. I argue that the prima facie state–content error this strategy seems to display is nothing but a case of “state–content error error,” i.e., the mistake of c…Read more
  •  19
    This volume traces the modern critical and performance history of this play, one of Shakespeare's most-loved and most-performed comedies. The essay focus on such modern concerns as feminism, deconstruction, textual theory, and queer theory.
  •  17
    Una crítica al realismo desde la teoría del significado
    Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 5 13. 1991.
    A Dummett's based critic of metaphysical realism based on semantic considerations pertaining to bivalence.
  •  183
    Semantic responsibility
    Philosophical Explorations 5 (1): 39-58. 2002.
    In this paper I attempt to develop a notion of responsibility (semantic responsibility) that is to the notion of belief what epistemic responsibility is to the notion of justification. 'Being semantically responsible' is shown to involve the fulfilment of cognitive duties which allow the agent to engage in the kind of reason-laden discourses which render her beliefs appropriately sensitive to correction. The concept of semantic responsibility suggests that the notion of belief found in contempor…Read more
  •  16
    Modularity, Relativism, and Neural Constructivism
    Cognitive Science Quarterly 2 (1): 93-106. 2002.
    Fodor claims that the modularity of mind helps undermine relativism in various forms. I shall show first, that the modular vision of mind provides insufficient support for the rejection of relativism, and second, that an alternative model may, in fact, provide a better empirical response to the relativist challenge.
  •  27
    Extruding Intentionality from the Metaphysical Flux
    Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Ai 11 501-518. 1999.
    On the Origin of Objects is, at heart, an extended search for a non-circular and nonreductive characterization of two key notions: intentionality and computation. Only a non-circular and non-reductive account of these key notions can, Smith believes, provide a secure platform for a proper understanding of the mind. The project has both a negative and a positive aspect. Negatively, Smith rejects views that attempt to identify the key notions with lower-level physical properties, arguing instead f…Read more
  •  28
    Mind and Supermind? Keith Frankish (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226): 139-142. 2007.
    This is a review of Mind and Supermind. By KEITH FRANKISH. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp xiv + 255. Price £45.00 (US $75.00). ISBN 0521 812038 (hardback).
  •  45
    O'Regan and Noe present a wonderfully detailed and comprehensive defense of a position whose broad outline we absolutely and unreservedly endorse. They are right, it seems to us, to stress the intimacy of conscious content and embodied action, and to counter the idea of a Grand Illusion with the image of an agent genuinely in touch, via active exploration, with the rich and varied visual scene. This is an enormously impressive achievement, and we hope that the comments that follow will be.
  •  10
    The Future of the Cognitive Revolution (review)
    Dialogue 39 (1): 183-185. 2000.
    One common factor underlying the set of disciplines clustered together under the label of Cognitive Science is a computational model of the mind. Cognitive capacities are to be treated as information-processing operations and to be characterized in computational terms. Computational processes are defined, in turn, in terms of operations on representations. For a few years, one of the most important debates in Cognitive Science has been whether the class of mechanisms to which cognizers belong an…Read more