•  5
    The Character of Galilean Evidence
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1): 125-134. 1986.
    Concerning evidence there are two important questions: (1) what is going to count as evidence? and (2) what are the appropriate means for employing evidence? These two problems pervade the analysis of the scientific process. They are with us as much today as in Galileo’s time. For example, with respect to contemporary arguments between Evolutionists and Scientific Creationists, if the issue is taken in its cognitive rather than its political dimension, the entire discussion turns on the criteria…Read more
  •  8
    The papers presented here derive from the 4th International Confe:--ence on History and Philosophy of Science held in Blacksburg, Virginia, U. S. A., November 2-6, 1982. The Conference was sponsored by the I nternational Union of History and Philosophy of Science and Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University (Virginia Tech). Particular thanks go to L. Jonathan Cohen, Secretary of the Union, as well as to Dean Henry Bauer of the College of Arts & Sciences, Wilfred Jewkes and the Center …Read more
  •  54
    Editorial Statement
    with Pieter E. Vermaas and Peter-Paul Verbeek
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 11 (1): 1-1. 2007.
  •  16
    Editorial Statement
    with Pieter E. Vermaas and Peter-Paul Verbeek
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 11 (1): 1-1. 2007.
  •  40
    Ethical Colonialism
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 7 (3): 32-38. 2004.
  •  16
    Section 2. Boundary Disagreements
    with Langdon Winner, Larry A. Hickman, Don Ihde, and Andrew Feenberg
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 24 (4): 9-28. 2020.
  •  1
    Book Review: Image and Logic (review)
    Science, Technology, and Human Values 24 (2): 295-298. 1999.
  •  35
    Influencing technological change
    Human Affairs 30 (4): 545-548. 2020.
    The philosophy of technology is not influencing technological change because there isn’t a single philosophy of technology. Philosophers of technology should be involved in technological change because we have something valuable to offer. But before we can get involved, we have to be accepted by those effecting the changes. That means we have to acquire the credentials necessary to establish our credibility. We have to get our hands dirty.
  •  6
    The Problems of Individuating Revolution (review)
    Behavior and Philosophy 15 (1): 83. 1987.
  •  12
    This book aims to spell out the consequences of taking the technologies behind the doing of science seriously.
  •  44
    Revolutions in science and refinements in the analysis of causation
    with Morton Tavel
    Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 8 (1): 48-62. 1977.
    Summary A sufficient condition for a revolution in physics is a change in the concept of cause. To demonstrate this, we examine three developments in physical theory. After informally characterizing a theory in terms of an heuristic and a set of equations, we show how tensions between these two dimensions lead to the development of alternative theoretical accounts. In each case the crucial move results in a refinement of our account of cause. All these refinements taken together result in the em…Read more
  •  16
    Focused on mapping out contemporary and future domains in philosophy of technology, this volume serves as an excellent, forward-looking resource in the field and in cognate areas of study. The 32 chapters, all of them appearing in print here for the first time, were written by both established scholars and fresh voices. They cover topics ranging from data discrimination and engineering design, to art and technology, space junk, and beyond. Spaces for the Future: A Companion to Philosophy of Tech…Read more
  • Theories of explanation
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 179 (4): 654-655. 1989.
  • New Perspectives on Galileo
    with Robert E. Butts
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (2): 195-199. 1980.
  •  11
    Letter from the Editor-in-Chief
    Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology 17 (3): 293-294. 2013.
  •  1
    Context Versus Processes
    In Byron Newberry, Carl Mitcham, Martin Meganck, Andrew Jamison, Christelle Didier & Steen Hyldgaard Christensen (eds.), Engineering Identities, Epistemologies and Values: Engineering Education and Practice in Context, Springer Verlag. 2015.
  •  1
    Review Article (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 7 (1): 122-128. 1991.
  • Tecnologia e ideologia
    Nuova Civiltà Delle Macchine 2 (2): 15-18. 1984.
  • An Analysis of Wilfrid Sellars' Theory of Justification as Explanation
    Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada). 1972.
  •  26
    Speak to Me
    Metascience 16 (1): 51-59. 2007.
  •  41
    The Epistemological Engine
    Philosophica 32 (n/a). 1983.
  •  22
    Wilfrid Sellars' Theory of Probability
    Philosophy Research Archives 2 445-482. 1976.
    Wilfrid Sellars attempts to deflect traditional objections to the straight rule of inductive acceptance by embedding it in a complicated system of levels. This system rests on a theory of probability in which the meaning of "probable" is reconstructed in the context of Sellars' general theory of practical reason. To say a statement is probable means, according to Sellars, that there is good reason for accepting the statement as true. In this paper I examine Sellars' attempt to resuscitate the st…Read more