•  21
    Dealing with Naive Relativism in the Philosophy Classroom
    Metaphilosophy 14 (2): 179-182. 2007.
  •  547
    Improving our aim
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24 (2). 1999.
    Bioethicists appearing in the media have been accused of "shooting from the hip" (Rachels, 1991). The criticism is sometimes justified. We identify some reasons our interactions with the press can have bad results and suggest remedies. In particular we describe a target (fostering better public dialogue), obstacles to hitting the target (such as intrinsic and accidental defects in our knowledge) and suggest some practical ways to surmont those obstacles (including seeking out ways to write or sp…Read more
  •  5
    Beast and Man
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 30 257-262. 1984.
  •  20
    The Demands of Deontology Are Not So Paradoxical
    Journal of Philosophical Research 16 407-410. 1991.
    The “paradox of deontology” depends partly upon ignoring the special responsibility each person has for her own actions, and partly upon ignoring the essential differences between refraining from X and persuading another to refrain. But only in part; the paradoxical situations schematized by Shaw can occasionally occur. When they do, his pragmatic defense of deontology is sound.
  •  12
    Rights, Killing, and Suffering (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 31 521-522. 1986.
  •  12
    Free Speech (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 31 519-521. 1986.
  •  8
    Wickedness (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 31 522-523. 1986.
  •  21
    Body Parts: Property Rights and the Ownership of Human Biological Materials
    with E. Richard Gold
    Hastings Center Report 28 (2): 42. 1998.
  •  31
    Bodies for Sale (review)
    Hastings Center Report 28 (2): 42. 1998.
  •  19
    The First BioethicistBioethics as Practice
    with Mark Kuczewski
    Hastings Center Report 33 (5): 45. 2003.
  •  86
    The Good Wife and Philosophy
    Open Court Publishing. 2013.
    Fifteen philosophers look at the deeper issues raised in the highly popular TV drama, including common morality, legal correctness and legal ethics, discussing the gray areas of legal battles and maneuvering. Original.
  • Because the medical humanities are multidisciplinary, participants tend to see one another's work through their own disciplinary lens. This can lead to misinterpretations.
  •  300
    A Larger Space for Moral Reflection
    Ethical Currents (53): 6-8. 1998.
    Margaret Urban Walker argues that hospital ethics committees should think of their task as "keeping moral space open." I develop her suggestion with analogies: Enlarge the windows (i.e., expand what counts as an ethical issue); add rooms and doors (i.e., choose particular issues to engage). Examples include confidentiality defined as information flow, and moral distress in the healthcare workplace.
  •  10
    Speaking Truth to Employers
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 8 (2): 199-203. 1997.
  •  27
    Open Hope as a Civic Virtue
    Social Philosophy Today 29 89-100. 2013.
    Hope as a virtue is an acquired disposition, shaped by reflection; as a civic virtue it must serve the good of the community. Ernst Bloch and Lord Buddha offer help in constructing such a virtue. Using a taxonomy developed by Darren Webb I distinguish open hope from goal-oriented hope, and use each thinker to develop the former. Bloch and Buddha are very different (and notoriously obscure; I do not attempt an exegesis). But they share a metaphysics of change, foundational for making any sense of…Read more
  •  26
    Goals of Ethics Consultation: Toward Clarity, Utility, and Fidelity
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 8 (2): 193-198. 1997.
  •  136
  •  61
    The Ways of Peace (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (2): 173-174. 1987.
  •  468
    Moral Distress in Healthcare
    Bioethics Forum 18 (1-2): 44-46. 2002.
    Moral distress is the sense that one must do, or cooperate in, what is wrong. It is paradigmatically faced by nurses, but it is almost a universal occupational hazard.
  •  47
    Rights, Killing, and Suffering (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 31 521-522. 1986.
  •  80
    My Client, My Enemy
    Professional Ethics, a Multidisciplinary Journal 3 (3): 27-46. 1994.
  •  82
    Caring; A Feminine Approach To Ethics and Moral Education (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 9 (1): 89-90. 1986.
  •  24
    Review essay / disgust, dignity, and a public intellectual
    Criminal Justice Ethics 24 (1): 52-57. 2005.
    Martha C. Nussbaum, Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton Nf: Princeton University Press, 2004, xv #;pl 413 pp
  •  350
    Elderhood—or old age, if one prefers—is a stage of life without much cultural meaning. It is generally viewed simply as a time of regrettable decline. Paying more attention to it, to its special pleasures and developmental achievements, will be helpful not only to elders but to those younger as well. I will argue that three existential tasks are central in elderhood, but also important at every other stage of adult life. I identify three: cherishing the present, accepting the past, and investing…Read more
  •  4
    Disgust, Dignity, and a Public Intellectual (review)
    Criminal Justice Ethics 24 (1): 52-57. 2005.
    Martha Nussbaum’s Hiding from Humanity is eloquent and thought-provoking. I criticize some of her central arguments, particularly her construal of disgust and her exposition of shame. But I applaud the book as a whole. It is possible that richness and engagement are more important in the work of public intellectuals than is technical precision. If so, Nussbaum has fulfilled her role. It is more likely that both qualities are important, but difficult to combine. In that case, we can still …Read more
  •  582
    Business Ethics and medical ethics are in principle compatible: In particular, the tools of business ethics can be useful to those doing healthcare ethics. Health care could be conducted as a business and maintain its moral core.
  •  71
    Privacy as a value and as a right
    Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (4): 309-317. 1986.
    Knowledge of others, then, has value; so does immunity from being known. The ability to extend one's knowledge has value; so does the ability to limit other's knowledge of oneself. I have claimed that no interest can count as a right unless it clearly outweighs opposing interests whose presence is logically entailed. I see no way to establish that my interest in not being known, simply as such, outweighs your desire to know about me. I acknowledge the intuitive attractiveness of such a position;…Read more
  •  24
    Humility
    Philosophical Books 35 (1): 60-62. 1994.
  •  58
    Beyond Moral Reasoning
    Teaching Philosophy 14 (4): 359-373. 1991.