•  5
    The Logic of Liberty
    Noûs 25 (2): 233-238. 1991.
  •  12
    Why You Should: The Pragmatics of Deontic Speech
    Noûs 27 (4): 527-530. 1993.
  •  19
    The Legal Philosophy of H. L. A. Hart: A Critical Appraisal
    with Michael Martin
    Philosophical Review 99 (2): 283. 1990.
  •  4
    The scope of privacy in law and ethics
    Law and Philosophy 5 (2). 1986.
  •  7
    Theory and Practice
    NYU Press. 1996.
    Contributors discuss the work of thinkers such as Cass Sunstein and Jeremy Waldron in their exploration of the relations between philosophical theories and everyday life. They elucidate major attempts to reconcile theory with practice in the Western tradition, from Herodotus to Heidegger, and discuss topics such as the role of theory in judicial decision-making and the political implication of theory. Of interest to philosophers, lawyers, and social scientists. Annotation copyright by Book News,…Read more
  •  35
    Critical Legal Studies and Liberalism
    Philosophical Topics 18 (1): 41-51. 1990.
  •  18
    Innocence Lost: An Examination of Inescapable Moral Wrong-Doing
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (2): 487-490. 1998.
  •  10
    Rawls and Rights
    with Rex Martin
    Noûs 21 (3): 445. 1987.
  •  25
    Uneasy Access: Privacy for Women in a Free Society
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 709. 1992.
  •  17
    The Problem of Conditional Obligation
    Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst. 1978.
  •  4
    Unionization in the Academy: Visions and Realities
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 2003.
    Unionization in the Academy presents an authoritative, balanced, and comprehensive treatment of academic unions—their history, purpose, and the conflicts they cause
  •  23
    Drug Testing Balancing Privacy and Public Safety
    Hastings Center Report 24 (2): 17-23. 1994.
    Although testing for substance abuse can be intrusive, inaccurate, and ineffective at ferreting out those who are a threat to others, it can be morally justified in certain carefully circumscribed cases.
  •  55
    I first discuss reasons for feminists to attend to the role of women in the military, despite past emphasis on antimilitarism. I then focus on the exclusion of women from combat duty, reviewing its sanction by the U.S. Supreme Court and the history of its adoption. I present arguments favoring the exclusion, defending strong replies to each, and demonstrate that reasoning from related cases and feminist analyses of equality explain why exclusion remains entrenched
  •  56
    The Priority of Privacy for Medical Information
    Social Philosophy and Policy 17 (2): 213. 2000.
    Individuals care about and guard their privacy intensely in many areas. With respect to patient medical records, people are exceedingly concerned about privacy protection, because they recognize that health care generates the most sensitive sorts of personal information. In an age of advancing technology, with the switch from paper medical files to massive computer databases, privacy protection for medical information poses a dramatic challenge. Given high-speed computers and Internet capabiliti…Read more
  •  111
    Free speech and offensive expression
    Social Philosophy and Policy 21 (2): 81-103. 2004.
    Free speech has historically been viewed as a special and preferred democratic value in the United States, by the public as well as by the legislatures and courts. In 1937, Justice Benjamin Cardozo wrote in Palko v. Connecticut that protection of speech is a “fundamental” liberty due to America's history, political and legal, and he recognized its importance, saying, “[F]reedom of thought and speech” is “the matrix, the indispensable condition, of nearly every other form of freedom.” It is likel…Read more
  •  82
    Conditional obligation and counterfactuals
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (1). 1981.
  •  52
    Moral rights: Conflicts and valid claims
    Philosophical Studies 54 (1). 1988.
    Most of us have certain intuitions about moral rights, at least partially captured by the ideas that: (A) rights carry special weight in moral argument; (B) persons retain their rights even when they are legitimately infringed; although (C) rights undoubtedly do conflict with one another, and are sometimes overridden as well by nonrights considerations. I show that Dworkin's remarks about rights allow us to affirm (A), (B), and (C), yet those remarks are extremely vague. I then argue that Feinbe…Read more
  •  82
    Privacy
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  38
    Defending the “private” in constitutional privacy
    Journal of Value Inquiry 21 (3): 171-184. 1987.
    Suppose we agree to reject the view that privacy has narrow scope and consequently is irrelevant to the constitutional privacy cases. We then have (at least) these two options: (1) We might further emphasize and draw out similarities between tort and constitutional privacy claims in order to develop a notion of privacy fundamental to informational and Fourth Amendment privacy concerns as well as the constitutional cases. We can cite examples indicating this is a promising position. Consider cons…Read more