•  25
    On Gaslighting
    Princeton University Press. 2024.
    A philosopher examines the complicated phenomenon of gaslighting “Gaslighting” is suddenly in everyone’s vocabulary. It’s written about, talked about, tweeted about, even sung about (in “Gaslighting” by The Chicks). It’s become shorthand for being manipulated by someone who insists that up is down, hot is cold, dark is light—someone who isn’t just lying about such things, but trying to drive you crazy. The term has its origins in a 1944 film in which a husband does exactly that to his wife, his …Read more
  •  94
    Happy to Unite, or Not?
    Philosophy Compass 1 (3): 290-302. 2006.
    At several key moments in his works, Hume draws our attention to the differences between two conceptions of philosophy. Deploying what were already then well‐worn metaphors, he calls these two “species” of philosophy “anatomy” and “painting.” Hume’s remarks about philosophical anatomy and painting have recently given rise to a number of scholarly debates. I focus here on just one of these debates: did Hume intend to combine anatomy and painting in some of his later works? Through an examination …Read more
  •  182
  •  10
    Tugendideale in Smiths Theorie der moralischen Gefühle
    In Hans-Peter Schütt & Christel Fricke (eds.), Adam Smith als Moralphilosoph, Berlin/new York. pp. 214-250. 2005.
  •  19
    Sympathy and Hume's Spectator‐Centered, Theory of Virtue
    In Elizabeth S. Radcliffe (ed.), A Companion to Hume, Blackwell. 2008.
    This chapter contains section titled: Humean Moral Sentiments as Responsibility Conferring Exclusion and Humean Moral Disapproval A Spectator's Standard of Virtue Looking Forward References Further Reading.
  •  777
    Turning up the lights on gaslighting
    Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1): 1-30. 2014.
  •  88
    Hume Studies Referees, 2002–2003
    with Donald Ainslie, Donald L. M. Baxter, Tom L. Beauchamp, Martin Bell, Richard Bett, John Bricke, Philip Bricker, Justin Broackes, and Stephen Buckle
    Hume Studies 29 (2): 403-404. 2003.
  •  65
    Hume Studies Referees, 2000-2001
    with Donald Ainslie, Karl Ameriks, Elizabeth Ashford, Martin Bell, Simon Blackburn, Martha Bolton, M. A. Box, Vere Chappell, and Rachel Cohan
    Hume Studies 27 (2): 371-372. 2001.
  •  3
    Hume's Peculiar Sentiments: The Evolution of Hume's Moral Philosophy
    Dissertation, The University of Chicago. 1997.
    This dissertation examines the evolution of David Hume's ethics, focusing on moral judgment, moral motivation and ethical normativity. In chapter one, I argue that previous scholars have missed a crucial distinction between two different sympathetic processes at work in the Treatise. The first sympathetic process, "particular sympathy" is analogous to ordinary empathy and variable in just the way empathy is, but a second, non-variable process, "extensive sympathy" is the source of our moral sent…Read more
  •  263
    Love as a reactive emotion
    with Adam Leite
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (245): 673-699. 2011.
    One variety of love is familiar in everyday life and qualifies in every reasonable sense as a reactive attitude. ‘Reactive love’ is paradigmatically (a) an affectionate attachment to another person, (b) appropriately felt as a non-self-interested response to particular kinds of morally laudable features of character expressed by the loved one in interaction with the lover, and (c) paradigmatically manifested in certain kinds of acts of goodwill and characteristic affective, desiderative and othe…Read more
  •  71
    Hume Studies Referees 2005–2006
    with Donald Ainslie, Lilli Alanen, Julia Annas, Margaret Atherton, Carla Bagnoli, Donald Baxter, Martin Bell, Richard Bett, and Colin Bird
    Hume Studies 32 (2): 391-393. 2006.
  •  359
    Sympathy and the project of Hume's second enquiry
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 83 (1): 45-80. 2001.
    More than two hundred years after its publication, David Hume's Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals is still widely regarded as either a footnote to the more philosophically interesting third book of the Treatise, or an abbreviated, more stylish, version of that earlier work. These standard interpretations are rather difficult to square with Hume's own assessment of the second Enquiry. Are we to think that Hume called the EPM “incomparably the best” of all his writings only because he pr…Read more
  •  139
    Although the implications of Hume's distinction between philosophical anatomy and painting have been the subject of lively scholarly debates, it is a puzzling fact that the details of the distinction itself have largely been a matter of interpretive presumption rather than debate. This would be unproblematic if Hume's views about these two species of philosophy were obvious, or if there were a rich standard interpretation of the distinction that we had little reason to doubt. But a careful revie…Read more
  •  81
    Hume Studies Referees, 2003–2004
    with Larry Arnhart, Carla Bagnoli, Martin Bell, Theodore Benditt, Christopher Berry, Deborah Boyle, John Bricke, Justin Broackes, and Janet Broughton
    Hume Studies 30 (2): 443-445. 2004.
  •  151
    Two portraits of the Humean moral agent
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (4). 2002.
    Among contemporary ethicists, Hume is perhaps best known for his views about morality’s practical import and his spectator-centered account of moral evaluation. Yet according to the so-called “spectator complaint”, these two aspects of Hume’s moral theory cannot be reconciled with one another. I argue that the answer to the spectator complaint lies in Hume’s account of “goodness” and “greatness of mind”. Through a discussion of these two virtues, Hume makes clear the connection between his views…Read more
  •  196
    Hume on cultural conflicts of values
    Philosophical Studies 94 (1-2): 173-187. 1999.