•  3
    In The Recovery of the Soul, Kenneth Rankin suggests that the current impasse over solutions to many philosophical problems is the result, in part, of a failure to consider how each of these problems bears on the rest. Rankin shows that a libertarian theory of free will, an A-theory of time, a corporealist theory of personal identity, and a non-relativist interpretation of the foundation of ethics all contribute to or are derived from a psychocentric form of physicalism. The proposed Modal Ident…Read more
  •  4
    A Metaphysical Confirmation of "Folk” Psychology
    Maritain Studies/Etudes Maritainiennes 9 135-143. 1993.
  •  10
    The Language of Time
    Philosophical Quarterly 19 (75): 176-177. 1969.
  •  8
    Essays on Freedom of Action
    Philosophical Quarterly 24 (95): 188-189. 1974.
  •  7
    A Critique of Jean-Paul Sartre’s Ontology
    Philosophical Quarterly 3 (11): 184-185. 1953.
  •  13
    The Disappearance of Introspection
    Noûs 25 (4): 567. 1991.
  • Choice and Chance
    Philosophy 38 (144): 188-188. 1963.
  •  61
    Critical notices (review)
    Mind 71 (281): 117-123. 1962.
  •  19
    Being in Time (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3): 114-115. 1993.
  •  59
  •  24
    Image-Talk: The Myth in the Mirror
    Philosophy 67 (260). 1992.
    A mirror image is not an image of a thing seen, but that thing seen in a different perspective.
  •  22
    McTaggart, Mereology, Substance and Change
    Dialogue 21 (1): 57-78. 1982.
    McTaggart maintained that, without the kind of change which events undergo in passing from the future through the present into the past, how things are would be fundamentally different from how they appear. More particularly Without A-change there could be no change at all. Without any change there could be no time. Without A-change there could be no time.
  •  16
    Image-Talk: The Myth in the Mirror: Discussion
    Philosophy 67 (260): 241-246. 1992.
  •  19
  •  19
  •  16
    A deterministic windmill
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41 (2). 1963.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  20
    Referential Indentifiers
    American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (3). 1964.
  •  2
    Kierkegaard und der Verfuhrer
    Philosophical Quarterly 2 (9): 375. 1952.
  • HITROW, G. J.: "The Natural Philosophy of Time" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 40 (n/a): 249. 1962.
  •  1
    TOMS, ERIC: "Being, negation and logic" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41 (n/a): 272. 1963.
  •  25
    McTaggart's Paradox: Two Parodies
    Philosophy 56 (217). 1981.
    To be truly provocative and outrageous the superior philosophical sophistry will commonly possess four somewhat adventitious features. I shall rate it as classic if it has all four. First, and least adventitiously, the argument will be crisp and initially seductive. Second, by the standard the sophistry sets direct rebuttal will be laborious and diffuse. Third, the recipe for the latter will prescribe that we pick out some hitherto unarticulated logical principle such that if the principle be tr…Read more
  •  24
    Past and future
    Philosophical Quarterly 17 (69): 317-333. 1967.
  •  6
    More on the deterministic windmill
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 42 (3). 1964.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  235
    Is the third man argument an inconsistent triad?
    Philosophical Quarterly 20 (81): 378-380. 1970.
    To understand the tma we should follow a rule of polemical force as well as a rule of validity. Following just the latter vlastos renders the explicit theory of forms and the two suppressed premises as an inconsistent triad. But the rule of polemical force indicates that the explicit theory is ambivalent. Just one f-Ness must be the basis, Either for any f thing being f, Or for any set of f things being just that set. It cannot be the basis for all f things being f
  •  17
    The Trinitarian Vision of P. F. Strawson
    Philosophy Research Archives 1164 745-771. 1976.
    Along with more frequently discussed theses, Strawson in his Chapter on Persons has maintained that the perceptual experience of the same subject could be causally dependent upon a multiplicity of bodies. But, without drastic revision, his effort to show in illustration that the visual experience of one subject might causally depend upon three different bodies is too fraught with difficulty to lend coherent support. When the difficulties are removed by revision, the truth of the thesis depends u…Read more
  •  66
    Doer and doing
    Mind 69 (275): 361-371. 1960.