•  1243
    Conditionals, Context, and the Suppression Effect
    Cognitive Science 41 (3): 540-589. 2017.
    Modus ponens is the argument from premises of the form If A, then B and A to the conclusion B. Nearly all participants agree that the modus ponens conclusion logically follows when the argument appears in this Basic form. However, adding a further premise can lower participants’ rate of agreement—an effect called suppression. We propose a theory of suppression that draws on contemporary ideas about conditional sentences in linguistics and philosophy. Semantically, the theory assumes that people …Read more
  •  1183
    Experimenting with (Conditional) Perfection
    In Stefan Kaufmann, David Over & Ghanshyam Sharma (eds.), Conditionals: Logic, Semantics, Psychology, . forthcoming.
    Conditional perfection is the phenomenon in which conditionals are strengthened to biconditionals. In some contexts, “If A, B” is understood as if it meant “A if and only if B.” We present and discuss a series of experiments designed to test one of the most promising pragmatic accounts of conditional perfection. This is the idea that conditional perfection is a form of exhaustification—that is a strengthening to an exhaustive reading, triggered by a question that the conditional answers. If a sp…Read more
  •  200
    How do we regard fictional people? How do they regard us?
    with Meghan M. Salomon-Amend
    Psychonomic Bulletin and Review. forthcoming.
    Readers assume that commonplace properties of the real world also hold in realistic fiction. They believe, for example, that the usual physical laws continue to apply. But controversy exists in theories of fiction about whether real individuals exist in the story’s world. Does Queen Victoria exist in the world of Jane Eyre, even though Victoria is not mentioned in it? The experiments we report here find that when participants are prompted to consider the world of a fictional individual (“Conside…Read more
  •  176
    Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations (edited book)
    with Jonathan Eric Adler
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    This interdisciplinary work is a collection of major essays on reasoning: deductive, inductive, abductive, belief revision, defeasible, cross cultural, conversational, and argumentative. They are each oriented toward contemporary empirical studies. The book focuses on foundational issues, including paradoxes, fallacies, and debates about the nature of rationality, the traditional modes of reasoning, as well as counterfactual and causal reasoning. It also includes chapters on the interface betwee…Read more
  •  123
    From numerical concepts to concepts of number
    with Amber Bloomfield and Jennifer Asmuth
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6): 623-642. 2008.
    Many experiments with infants suggest that they possess quantitative abilities, and many experimentalists believe that these abilities set the stage for later mathematics: natural numbers and arithmetic. However, the connection between these early and later skills is far from obvious. We evaluate two possible routes to mathematics and argue that neither is sufficient: (1) We first sketch what we think is the most likely model for infant abilities in this domain, and we examine proposals for extr…Read more
  •  86
    Identity, Causality, and Pronoun Ambiguity
    with Eyal Sagi
    Topics in Cognitive Science 6 (4): 663-680. 2014.
    This article looks at the way people determine the antecedent of a pronoun in sentence pairs, such as: Albert invited Ron to dinner. He spent hours cleaning the house. The experiment reported here is motivated by the idea that such judgments depend on reasoning about identity . Because the identity of an individual over time depends on the causal-historical path connecting the stages of the individual, the correct antecedent will also depend on causal connections. The experiment varied how likel…Read more
  •  85
    Reasoning About Truth in First-Order Logic
    with Claes Strannegård, Fredrik Engström, and Abdul Rahim Nizamani
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 22 (1): 115-137. 2013.
    First, we describe a psychological experiment in which the participants were asked to determine whether sentences of first-order logic were true or false in finite graphs. Second, we define two proof systems for reasoning about truth and falsity in first-order logic. These proof systems feature explicit models of cognitive resources such as declarative memory, procedural memory, working memory, and sensory memory. Third, we describe a computer program that is used to find the smallest proofs in …Read more
  •  75
    Inductive judgments about natural categories
    Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 14 (6): 665-681. 1975.
    The present study examined the effects of semantic structure on simple inductive judgments about category members. For a particular category, subjects were told that one of the species had a given property and were asked to estimate the proportion of instances in the other species that possessed the property. The results indicated that category structure—in particular, the typicality of the species—influenced subjects' judgments. These results were interpreted by models based on the following as…Read more
  •  74
    Combining Prototypes: A Selective Modification Model
    with Edward E. Smith, Daniel N. Osherson, and Margaret Keane
    Cognitive Science 12 (4): 485-527. 1988.
  •  73
    This special issue of Informal Logic brings together a num-ber of traditions from the psychology and philosophy of argument. Psycho-logists’ interest in argument typically arises in understanding how indivi-duals form and change their beliefs. Thus, theories of argument can serve as models of the structure of justi-fications for belief, as methods of diagnosing errors in beliefs, and as prototypes for learning. The articles in this issue illustrate all three of these connections
  •  72
    The current status of research on concept combination
    Mind and Language 10 (1-2): 72-104. 1995.
    Understanding novel phrases (e.g. upside‐down daisy) and classifying objects in categories named by phrases ought to have common properties, but you'd never know it from current theories. The best candidate for both jobs is the Theory Theory, but it faces difficulties when theories are impoverished. A potential solution is a dual approach that couples theories (representations‐about categories) with fixed mentalese expressions (representations‐of categories). Both representations combine informa…Read more
  •  70
    Inference and Explanation in Counterfactual Reasoning
    Cognitive Science 37 (6): 1107-1135. 2013.
    This article reports results from two studies of how people answer counterfactual questions about simple machines. Participants learned about devices that have a specific configuration of components, and they answered questions of the form “If component X had not operated [failed], would component Y have operated?” The data from these studies indicate that participants were sensitive to the way in which the antecedent state is described—whether component X “had not operated” or “had failed.” Ans…Read more
  •  58
    Two causal theories of counterfactual conditionals
    Cognitive Science 34 (2): 175-221. 2010.
    Bayes nets are formal representations of causal systems that many psychologists have claimed as plausible mental representations. One purported advantage of Bayes nets is that they may provide a theory of counterfactual conditionals, such as If Calvin had been at the party, Miriam would have left early. This article compares two proposed Bayes net theories as models of people's understanding of counterfactuals. Experiments 1-3 show that neither theory makes correct predictions about backtracking…Read more
  •  57
    Dissonances in theories of number understanding
    with Amber Bloomfield and Jennifer Asmuth
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6): 671-687. 2008.
    Traditional theories of how children learn the positive integers start from infants' abilities in detecting the quantity of physical objects. Our target article examined this view and found no plausible accounts of such development. Most of our commentators appear to agree that no adequate developmental theory is presently available, but they attempt to hold onto a role for early enumeration. Although some defend the traditional theories, others introduce new basic quantitative abilities, new me…Read more
  •  56
    Explanation and Evidence in Informal Argument
    with Sarah K. Brem
    Cognitive Science 24 (4): 573-604. 2000.
    A substantial body of evidence shows that people tend to rely too heavily on explanations when trying to justify an opinion. Some research suggests these errors may arise from an inability to distinguish between explanations and the evidence that bears upon them. We examine an alternative account, that many people do distinguish between explanations and evidence, but rely more heavily on unsubstantiated explanations when evidence is scarce or absent. We examine the philosophical and psychologica…Read more
  •  52
    Rebooting the bootstrap argument: Two puzzles for bootstrap theories of concept development
    with Susan J. Hespos
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (3): 145. 2011.
    The Origin of Concepts sets out an impressive defense of the view that children construct entirely new systems of concepts. We offer here two questions about this theory. First, why doesn't the bootstrapping process provide a pattern for translating between the old and new systems, contradicting their claimed incommensurability? Second, can the bootstrapping process properly distinguish meaning change from belief change?
  •  44
    Tracing the identity of objects
    with Sergey Blok and George Newman
    Psychological Review 113 (1): 1-30. 2006.
    This article considers how people judge the identity of objects (e.g., how people decide that a description of an object at one time, t₀, belongs to the same object as a description of it at another time, t₁). The authors propose a causal continuer model for these judgments, based on an earlier theory by Nozick (1981). According to this model, the 2 descriptions belong to the same object if (a) the object at t₁ is among those that are causally close enough to be genuine continuers of the origina…Read more
  •  40
    Structure and process in semantic memory: A featural model for semantic decisions
    with Edward E. Smith and Edward J. Shoben
    Psychological Review 81 (3): 214-241. 1974.
  •  36
    Circular reasoning
    Cognitive Science 26 (6): 767-795. 2002.
    Good informal arguments offer justification for their conclusions. They go wrong if the justifications double back, rendering the arguments circular. Circularity, however, is not necessarily a single property of an argument, but may depend on (a) whether the argument repeats an earlier claim, (b) whether the repetition occurs within the same line of justification, and (c) whether the claim is properly grounded in agreed‐upon information. The experiments reported here examine whether people take …Read more
  •  36
    Sortal terms, such as table or horse, are count nouns (akin to a basic-level terms). According to some theories, the meaning of sortals provides conditions for telling objects apart (individuating objects, e.g., telling one table from a second) and for identifying objects over time (e.g., determining that a particular horse at one time is the same horse at another). A number of psychologists have proposed that sortal concepts likewise provide psychologically real conditions for individuating and…Read more
  •  35
    Can statistical learning bootstrap the integers?
    with Jennifer Asmuth and Amber Bloomfield
    Cognition 128 (3): 320-330. 2013.
  •  32
    Do children learn the integers by induction?
    with Jennifer Asmuth and Amber Bloomfield
    Cognition 106 (2): 940-951. 2008.
  •  32
    Similarity as an explanatory construct
    with Steven A. Sloman
    Cognition 65 (2-3): 87-101. 1998.
  •  30
    Out of sorts? Some remedies for theories of object concepts: A reply to Rhemtulla and Xu (2007)
    with Sergey V. Blok and George E. Newman
    Psychological Review 114 (4): 1096-1102. 2007.
  •  29
    Core Cognition and its Aftermath
    Philosophical Topics 45 (1): 157-179. 2017.
    A current and very influential theory in psychology holds that infants have innate, perceptually informed systems that endow them with surprisingly high-level concepts—for example, concepts of cardinality and causality. Proponents of core cognition hold that these initial concepts then provide the building blocks for later adult ideas within these domains. This paper reviews the evidence for core cognition and argues that these systems aren’t sufficient to explain how children learn their way to…Read more
  •  28
    Folk psychology of mental activities
    with Frederick G. Conrad
    Psychological Review 96 (2): 187-207. 1989.
    A central aspect of people's beliefs about the mind is that mental activities—for example, thinking, reasoning, and problem solving—are interrelated, with some activities being kinds or parts of others. In common-sense psychology, reasoning is a kind of thinking and reasoning is part of problem solving. People's conceptions of these mental kinds and parts can furnish clues to the ordinary meaning of these terms and to the differences between folk and scientific psychology. In this article, we us…Read more
  •  28
    Identity is a transitive relation, according to all standard accounts. Necessarily, if x = y and y = z, then x = z. However, people sometimes say that two objects, x and z, are the same as a third, y, even when x and z have different properties (thus, x = y and y = z, but x ≠ z). In the present experiments, participants read stories about an iceberg that breaks into two icebergs, one to the east and the other to the west. Many participants (32–54%, in baseline conditions across experiments) deci…Read more