• PhilPeople
  • PhilPapers
  • PhilArchive
  • PhilEvents
  • PhilJobs
  • Sign in
PhilPeople
 
  • Sign in
  • News Feed
  • Find Philosophers
  • Departments
  • Radar
  • Help
 

Drag to reposition

Mark Migotti
University of Calgary
  •  Home
  •  Publications
    38
    • Most Recent
    • Most Downloaded
    • Topics
  •  Events
    2
  •  News and Updates
    39
  •  My Philosophical Views

 More details
  • University of Calgary
    Department of Philosophy
    Professor
Yale University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1991
Calgary, Alberta, Canada
Areas of Specialization
19th Century Philosophy
20th Century Philosophy
European Philosophy
Areas of Interest
Epistemology
Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
  • All publications (38)
  •  7
    Who Are We? And How Do We Manage to Construct All these Objects? On Nietzsche’s Metaphysics of Material Objects
    Philosophia 1-10. forthcoming.
  •  45
    Truth, Rationality and Pragmatism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2): 287-310. 2004.
    Truth, Rationality and Pragmatism [TRP] presents the fruits of Christopher Hookway’s thinking about the philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce since the publication of Peirce in 1985. Unlike the earlier work, this ‘does not pretend to be a general introduction to Peirce’s philosophy [but]... deals [instead] with a range of important and central issues in more detail than was possible in that volume’. As his title indicates, Hookway’s chief aim is to articulate pragmatism’s most promising ideas abo…Read more
    Truth, Rationality and Pragmatism [TRP] presents the fruits of Christopher Hookway’s thinking about the philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce since the publication of Peirce in 1985. Unlike the earlier work, this ‘does not pretend to be a general introduction to Peirce’s philosophy [but]... deals [instead] with a range of important and central issues in more detail than was possible in that volume’. As his title indicates, Hookway’s chief aim is to articulate pragmatism’s most promising ideas about the nature of truth and rationality—well, as just noted, for ‘pragmatism’ read ‘Peirce’; but the wording of the title is not inappropriate given the regular use of James and Dewey as foils for interpreting Peirce.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  6
    The Cambridge Companion to Peirce Edited by Cheryl Misak Cambridge Companions New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004, xi + 362 pp., $70.00, $25.99 paper (review)
    Dialogue 45 (4): 813-816. 2006.
  •  34
    On the Very Idea of Sex with Robots
    with Nicole Wyatt
    In John Danaher & Neil McArthur (eds.), Robot Sex: Social Implications and Ethical, Mit. pp. 15-27. 2018.
    In this chapter, we focus on the simple sounding question: What is it to have sex? On the assumption that having sex is what you do with all and only your sexual part-ners, this offers a way of focusing the question: What would it take for a sex robot to be a sex partner? In order to understand the significance of the development of robots with whom (or which) we can have sex, we need to know what it is to have sex with a robot. And in order to know this, we have to know what it is to have sex, …Read more
    In this chapter, we focus on the simple sounding question: What is it to have sex? On the assumption that having sex is what you do with all and only your sexual part-ners, this offers a way of focusing the question: What would it take for a sex robot to be a sex partner? In order to understand the significance of the development of robots with whom (or which) we can have sex, we need to know what it is to have sex with a robot. And in order to know this, we have to know what it is to have sex, period. In the bulk of the chapter, we develop an account of shared sexual agency we think is a plausible precondition of genuinely having sex. In the final section, we remark briefly on the issue of what it would take to form a sexual we (as we call it) with a robot. For if we can do this, we can probably have sex with robots; but if we can’t, we can’t.
    Defining Sexual Activity
  •  1
    The Early Nietzsche and the Question of Redemption
    Dissertation, Yale University. 1991.
    This dissertation attempts to establish that Nietzsche's philosophical development from 1864 to 1870 is directed towards finding a satisfactory way to redeem the sufferings of life immanently, that is, without appeal to a state of perfect being beyond the grave. I argue that this stage of his thinking culminates in the belief that the project of self-expressive self-determination was a satisfactory source of immanent redemption, and I therefore label this enterprise the project of redemptive sel…Read more
    This dissertation attempts to establish that Nietzsche's philosophical development from 1864 to 1870 is directed towards finding a satisfactory way to redeem the sufferings of life immanently, that is, without appeal to a state of perfect being beyond the grave. I argue that this stage of his thinking culminates in the belief that the project of self-expressive self-determination was a satisfactory source of immanent redemption, and I therefore label this enterprise the project of redemptive self-determination. ;In the first of the dissertation's three parts I show how Nietzsche's confrontation with Schopenhauer's pessimism led him to believe that an acceptable practical philosophy--that is, a set of maxims prescribing or prohibiting the direction of one's energies towards the achievement of certain ends--had to be compatible with atheism and metaphysical pessimism . In part two I explain what redemptive self-determination is and argue for its presence in Nietzsche's thinking during the period covered. And in part three I show how his commitment to redemptive self-determination shaped his views of the promise and purpose of classical philology and the nature and death of Greek tragedy
    Friedrich Nietzsche
  •  5
    Friedrich Nietzsche: His Life and Thought (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 30 (4): 122-123. 1998.
  •  26
    History of Philosophy
    Philosophical Books 45 (3): 228-238. 2004.
  •  37
    Unmodern Observations
    International Philosophical Quarterly 31 (3): 367-369. 1991.
  •  33
    Sensuality and Its Discontents
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 44 (2): 315-328. 2013.
    Friedrich Nietzsche
  •  29
    Peirce's double-aspect theory of truth
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (sup1): 75-108. 1998.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  1
    Michael Hymers, Philosophy and its Epistemic Neuroses Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 21 (3): 182-184. 2001.
  •  27
    Discussion of Hymers’s Philosophy and Its Epistemic Neuroses
    Dialogue 43 (3): 587-594. 2004.
    Epistemology, General Works
  •  36
    Self-Determination, Self-Expression, and Self-Knowledge
    The Personalist Forum 8 (Supplement): 233-242. 1992.
    Epistemology of Mind
  •  18
    Rorty and His Critics (review)
    Dialogue 41 (1): 208-213. 2002.
    In the 1960s, Richard Rorty's public image was that of a rising officer in the advancing army of analytic philosophy. Then, in 1979, he published Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, in the wake of which all hell broke loose. Since that time, he has become a renowned neopragmatist enfant terrible, been called the most interesting philosopher in the world by Harold Bloom, dismissed as beneath discussion by most of the rank and file among his erstwhile analytic brethren, and now selected as the su…Read more
    In the 1960s, Richard Rorty's public image was that of a rising officer in the advancing army of analytic philosophy. Then, in 1979, he published Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, in the wake of which all hell broke loose. Since that time, he has become a renowned neopragmatist enfant terrible, been called the most interesting philosopher in the world by Harold Bloom, dismissed as beneath discussion by most of the rank and file among his erstwhile analytic brethren, and now selected as the subject of this ninth volume in Blackwell's Philosophers and Their Critics series.
    Philosophy of MindEliminative MaterialismRichard Rorty
  •  8
    No Title available: Dialogue
    Dialogue 45 (4): 813-816. 2006.
  • For the sake of knowledge and the love of truth : Susan Haack between sacred enthusiasm and sophisticated disillusionment
    In Cornelis De Waal (ed.), Susan Haack: A Lady of Distinctions: The Philosopher Responds to Critics, Prometheus Books. 2007.
  •  44
    All kinds of promises
    Ethics 114 (1): 60-87. 2003.
    Promises
  •  134
    Slave morality, socrates, and the bushmen: A reading of the first essay of on the genealogy of morals
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 745-779. 1998.
    This paper raises three questions: (1) Can Nietzsche provide a satisfactory account of how the slave revolt could have begun to "poison the consciences" of masters? (2) Does Nietzsche's affinity for "master values" preclude him from acknowledging claims of justice that rest upon a sense of equality among human beings? and (3) How does Nietzsche's story fare when looked on as (at least in part) an empirical hypothesis? The first question is answered in the affirmative, the second in the negative,…Read more
    This paper raises three questions: (1) Can Nietzsche provide a satisfactory account of how the slave revolt could have begun to "poison the consciences" of masters? (2) Does Nietzsche's affinity for "master values" preclude him from acknowledging claims of justice that rest upon a sense of equality among human beings? and (3) How does Nietzsche's story fare when looked on as (at least in part) an empirical hypothesis? The first question is answered in the affirmative, the second in the negative, and the third with the verdict "quite well". Nietzsche's interpretation of Socrates is held to vindicate the affirmative answer to question one; his conception of nobility as spontaneously self-affirming to justify the negative answer to question two, and historical, anthropological and etymological evidence to support the favorable answer to question three
    SocratesNietzsche's Works
  •  19
    Peirce's First Rule of Reason and the Bad Faith of Rortian Post-Philosophy
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 31 (1). 1995.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  27
    Minutes of the Business Meeting Charles Sanders Peirce Society 28 December 2004
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41 (3): 725-728. 2005.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  7
    Discussion of Hymers’s Philosophy and Its Epistemic Neuroses
    Dialogue 43 (3): 587-594. 2004.
  •  23
    The cambridge companion to Peirce
    Dialogue 45 (4): 813-816. 2006.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  32
    Review: Minutes of the business meeting: Charles Sanders Peirce society. 28 december 2006 (review)
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42 (3): 459-462. 2006.
    Charles Sanders Peirce
  •  22
    Not Your Grandfather’s Genealogy: How to Read GM III
    Journal of Value Inquiry 49 (3): 329-351. 2015.
    Value TheoryNietzsche: Genealogy of MoralsSocial and Political Philosophy
  •  15
    Luther's Word on Man's Will: A Case Study in Comparative Intellectual History
    Religious Studies 20 (4). 1984.
    Philosophy of ReligionSpecific Religions
  •  16
    Correspondence and Disquotation: An Essay on the Nature of Truth
    Philosophical Books 36 (4): 270-272. 1995.
    Correspondence Theory of Truth
  •  11
    Slave Morality, Socrates, and the Bushmen: A Reading of the First Essay of On the Genealogy of Morals
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 745-779. 1998.
    This paper raises three questions: Can Nietzsche provide a satisfactory account of how the slave revolt could have begun to "poison the consciences" of masters? Does Nietzsche's affinity for "master values" preclude him from acknowledging claims of justice that rest upon a sense of equality among human beings? and How does Nietzsche's story fare when looked on as an empirical hypothesis? The first question is answered in the affirmative, the second in the negative, and the third with the verdict…Read more
    This paper raises three questions: Can Nietzsche provide a satisfactory account of how the slave revolt could have begun to "poison the consciences" of masters? Does Nietzsche's affinity for "master values" preclude him from acknowledging claims of justice that rest upon a sense of equality among human beings? and How does Nietzsche's story fare when looked on as an empirical hypothesis? The first question is answered in the affirmative, the second in the negative, and the third with the verdict "quite well". Nietzsche's interpretation of Socrates is held to vindicate the affirmative answer to question one; his conception of nobility as spontaneously self-affirming to justify the negative answer to question two, and historical, anthropological and etymological evidence to support the favorable answer to question three.
  •  44
    Pragmatism, Genealogy, and Truth
    Dialogue 48 (1): 185. 2009.
    American Pragmatism
  •  10
    Nietzsche, Psychology, and First Philosophy, by Robert Pippin
    Mind 124 (496): 1359-1363. 2015.
    German Philosophy
  •  23
    Friedrich Nietzsche
    International Studies in Philosophy 30 (4): 122-123. 1998.
    Friedrich Nietzsche
  • Prev.
  • 1
  • 2
  • Next
PhilPeople logo

On this site

  • Find a philosopher
  • Find a department
  • The Radar
  • Index of professional philosophers
  • Index of departments
  • Help
  • Acknowledgments
  • Careers
  • Contact us
  • Terms and conditions

Brought to you by

  • The PhilPapers Foundation
  • The American Philosophical Association
  • Centre for Digital Philosophy, Western University
PhilPeople is currently in Beta Sponsored by the PhilPapers Foundation and the American Philosophical Association
Feedback