•  947
    Machine Ethics (edited book)
    Cambridge Univ. Press. 2011.
    The essays in this volume represent the first steps by philosophers and artificial intelligence researchers toward explaining why it is necessary to add an ...
  •  426
    Embodied cognition: A field guide
    Artificial Intelligence 149 (1): 91-130. 2003.
    The nature of cognition is being re-considered. Instead of emphasizing formal operations on abstract symbols, the new approach foregrounds the fact that cognition is, rather, a situated activity, and suggests that thinking beings ought therefore be considered first and foremost as acting beings. The essay reviews recent work in Embodied Cognition, provides a concise guide to its principles, attitudes and goals, and identifies the physical grounding project as its central research focus
  •  278
    To accept that cognition is embodied is to question many of the beliefs traditionally held by cognitive scientists. One key question regards the localization of cognitive faculties. Here we argue that for cognition to be embodied and sometimes embedded, means that the cognitive faculty cannot be localized in a brain area alone. We review recent research on neural reuse, the 1/f structure of human activity, tool use, group cognition, and social coordination dynamics that we believe demonstrates h…Read more
  •  227
    Abstract: The massive redeployment hypothesis (MRH) is a theory about the functional topography of the human brain, offering a middle course between strict localization on the one hand, and holism on the other. Central to MRH is the claim that cognitive evolution proceeded in a way analogous to component reuse in software engineering, whereby existing components-originally developed to serve some specific purpose-were used for new purposes and combined to support new capacities, without disrupti…Read more
  •  200
    The massive redeployment hypothesis and the functional topography of the brain
    Philosophical Psychology 21 (2): 143-174. 2008.
    This essay introduces the massive redeployment hypothesis, an account of the functional organization of the brain that centrally features the fact that brain areas are typically employed to support numerous functions. The central contribution of the essay is to outline a middle course between strict localization on the one hand, and holism on the other, in such a way as to account for the supporting data on both sides of the argument. The massive redeployment hypothesis is supported by case stud…Read more
  •  198
    Cognitive science and epistemic openness
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 5 (2): 125-154. 2006.
    b>. Recent findings in cognitive science suggest that the epistemic subject is more complex and epistemically porous than is generally pictured. Human knowers are open to the world via multiple channels, each operating for particular purposes and according to its own logic. These findings need to be understood and addressed by the philosophical community. The current essay argues that one consequence of the new findings is to invalidate certain arguments for epistemic anti-realism
  •  197
    The status of machine ethics: A report from the AAAI symposium (review)
    Minds and Machines 17 (1): 1-10. 2007.
      This paper is a summary and evaluation of work presented at the AAAI 2005 Fall Symposium on Machine Ethics that brought together participants from the fields of Computer Science and Philosophy to the end of clarifying the nature of this newly emerging field and discussing different approaches one could take towards realizing the ultimate goal of creating an ethical machine
  •  136
    Mining the Brain for a New Taxonomy of the Mind
    Philosophy Compass 10 (1): 68-77. 2015.
    In this paper, I summarize an emerging debate in the cognitive sciences over the right taxonomy for understanding cognition – the right theory of and vocabulary for describing the structure of the mind – and the proper role of neuroscientific evidence in specifying this taxonomy. In part because the discussion clearly entails a deep reconsideration of the supposed autonomy of psychology from neuroscience, this is a debate in which philosophers should be interested, with which they should be fami…Read more
  •  91
    In: B. Hardy-Vallee & N. Payette, eds. Beyond the brain: embodied, situated & distributed cognition. (Cambridge: Cambridge Scholar’s Press), in press. Abstract: In this article, I do three main things: 1. First, I introduce an approach to the mind motivated primarily by evolutionary considerations. I do that by laying out four principles for the study of the mind from an evolutionary perspective, and four predictions that they suggest. This evolutionary perspective is completely compatible with,…Read more
  •  83
    Reuse of identified neurons in multiple neural circuits
    with Jeremy E. Niven and Lars Chittka
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4): 285. 2010.
    The growing recognition by cognitive neuroscientists that areas of vertebrate brains may be reused for multiple purposes either functionally during development or during evolution echoes a similar realization made by neuroscientists working on invertebrates. Because of these animals' relatively more accessible nervous systems, neuronal reuse can be examined at the level of individual identified neurons and fully characterized neural circuits
  •  83
    The Leabra architecture: Specialization without modularity
    with Alexander A. Petrov, David J. Jilk, and Randall C. O'Reilly
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4): 286-287. 2010.
    The posterior cortex, hippocampus, and prefrontal cortex in the Leabra architecture are specialized in terms of various neural parameters, and thus are predilections for learning and processing, but domain-general in terms of cognitive functions such as face recognition. Also, these areas are not encapsulated and violate Fodorian criteria for modularity. Anderson's terminology obscures these important points, but we applaud his overall message.
  •  68
    What we need is better theory, not more data
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (2): 125-126. 2006.
    Although I find Blair's case for arguing for the distinction between fluid cognitive functions and general intelligence less than compelling, I believe him. However, I also believe that what is required next is a theory of both general intelligence and fluid cognitive functions that articulates the distinction. In the absence of this, more data, particularly of the neuroscience variety, is likely to stall rather than advance progress. (Published Online April 5 2006).
  •  67
    Prelinguistic agents will form only egocentric representations
    with Tim Oates
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3): 284-285. 2003.
    The representations formed by the ventral and dorsal streams of a prelinguistic agent will tend to be too qualitatively similar to support the distinct roles required by PREDICATE(x) structure. We suggest that the attachment of qualities to objects is not a product of the combination of these separate processing streams, but is instead a part of the processing required in each. In addition, we suggest that the formation of objective predicates is inextricably bound up with the emergence of langu…Read more
  •  58
    How Machines Can Advance Ethics
    with Susan Leigh Anderson
    Philosophy Now 72 17-19. 2009.
  •  57
    When things go badly, we notice that something is amiss, figure out what went wrong and why, and attempt to repair the problem. Artificial systems depend on their human designers to program in responses to every eventuality and therefore typically don’t even notice when things go wrong, following their programming over the proverbial, and in some cases literal, cliff. This article describes our work on the Meta-Cognitive Loop, a domain-general approach to giving artificial systems the ability to…Read more
  •  52
    Predictive validity of the N2 and P3 ERP components to executive functioning in children: a latent-variable analysis
    with Christopher R. Brydges, Allison M. Fox, and Corinne L. Reid
    Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8. 2014.
  •  40
  •  33
    We agree with Heyes that an explanation of human uniqueness must appeal to cultural evolution, and not just genes. Her account, though, focuses narrowly on internal cognitive mechanisms. This causes her to mischaracterize human behavior and to overlook the role of material culture. A more powerful account would view cognitive gadgets as spanning organisms and their (shared) environments.
  •  33
  •  32
    Drawing from two strands of ecological psychology, we suggest that even if social robots are interactive depictions, people need not mentally represent them as such. Rather, people can engage with the opportunities for action or affordances that social robots offer to them. These affordances are constrained by the larger sociocultural settings within which human–robot interactions occur.
  •  28
    The emperor has no blanket!
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45. 2022.
    While we applaud Bruineberg et al.'s analysis of the differences between Markov blankets and Friston blankets, we think it is not carried out to its ultimate consequences. There are reasons to think that, once Friston blankets are accepted as a theoretical construct, they do not do the work proponents of free energy principle (FEP) attribute to them. The emperor is indeed naked.
  •  27
    Are interactive specialization and massive redeployment compatible?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (3): 331-334. 2008.
    I offer a simple method for further investigating the Interactive Specialization framework, and some data that may or may not be compatible with the approach, depending on the precise meaning of Findings from my lab indicate that, while networks of brain areas cooperate in specialized ways to support cognitive functions, individual brain areas participate in many such networks, in different cognitive domains.
  •  21
    The stimulus-response crisis
    with Robyn Wilford, Juan Ardila-Cifuentes, and Edward Baggs
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45. 2022.
    Yarkoni correctly recognizes that one reason for psychology's generalizability crisis is the failure to account for variance within experiments. We argue that this problem, and the generalizability crisis broadly, is a necessary consequence of the stimulus-response paradigm widely used in psychology research. We point to another methodology, perturbation experiments, as a remedy that is not vulnerable to the same problems.
  •  18
    The Massive Redeployment Hypothesis and the Functional Topography of the Brain
    Philosophical Psychology 20 (2): 143-174. 2007.
    This essay introduces the massive redeployment hypothesis, an account of the functional organization of the brain that centrally features the fact that brain areas are typically employed to support numerous functions. The central contribution of the essay is to outline a middle course between strict localization on the one hand, and holism on the other, in such a way as to account for the supporting data on both sides of the argument. The massive redeployment hypothesis is supported by case stud…Read more
  •  10
    Active logic semantics for a single agent in a static world
    with Walid Gomaa, John Grant, and Don Perlis
    Artificial Intelligence 172 (8-9): 1045-1063. 2008.
  •  9
    Frequency-tagging in memory - context or reactivation?
    with Wimber Maria, Hanslmayr Simon, and Henson Rik
    Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9. 2015.
  •  9
    Why is AI so scary?
    Artificial Intelligence 169 (2): 201-208. 2005.