•  40
    Scientific Philosophy from Helmholtz to Carnap and Quine
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 16 1-11. 2012.
    The concept of a “scientific philosophy” first developed in the mid nineteenth century, as a reaction against what was viewed as the excessively speculative and metaphysical character of post-Kantian German idealism. One of the primary intellectual models of this movement was a celebrated address by Hermann von Helmholtz, “Über das Sehen des Menschen,” delivered at the dedication of a monument to Kant at Königsberg in 1855. Helmholtz begins by asking, on behalf of the audience, why a natural sci…Read more
  • Space in Kantian idealism
    In Andrew Janiak (ed.), Space: a history, Oxford University Press. 2020.
  •  103
  •  6
    Martin Heidegger--die Falte der Sprache (edited book)
    with Angelika Seppi and André Scala
    Verlag Turia + Kant. 2017.
  •  105
    Theoretical Philosophy After 1781 (edited book)
    with Henry E. Allison, Peter Heath, and Gary Hatfield
    Cambridge University Press. 2010.
    This volume, originally published in 2002, assembles the historical sequence of writings that Kant published between 1783 and 1796 to popularize, summarize, amplify and defend the doctrines of his masterpiece, the Critique of Pure Reason of 1781. The best known of them, the Prolegomena, is often recommended to beginning students, but the other texts are also vintage Kant and are important sources for a fully rounded picture of Kant's intellectual development. As with other volumes in the series …Read more
  •  137
    Addressing a wide range of topics, from Newton to Post-Kuhnian philosophy of science, these essays critically examine themes that have been central to the influential work of philosopher Michael Friedman.
  •  265
    Reconsidering Logical Positivism
    Cambridge University Press. 1999.
    In this collection of essays one of the preeminent philosophers of science writing offers a reinterpretation of the enduring significance of logical positivism, the revolutionary philosophical movement centered around the Vienna Circle in the 1920s and 30s. Michael Friedman argues that the logical positivists were radicals not by presenting a new version of empiricism but rather by offering a new conception of a priori knowledge and its role in empirical knowledge. This collection will be mandat…Read more
  •  34
    This book introduces a new approach to the issue of radical scientific revolutions, or "paradigm-shifts," given prominence in the work of Thomas Kuhn. The book articulates a dynamical and historicized version of the conception of scientific a priori principles first developed by the philosopher Immanuel Kant. This approach defends the Enlightenment ideal of scientific objectivity and universality while simultaneously doing justice to the revolutionary changes within the sciences that have since …Read more
  •  37
    In this insightful study of the common origins of analytic and continental philosophy, Friedman looks at how social and political events intertwined and influenced philosophy during the early twentieth century, ultimately giving rise to the two very different schools of thought. He shows how these two approaches, now practiced largely in isolation from one another, were once opposing tendencies within a common discussion. Already polarized by their philosophical disagreements, these approaches w…Read more
  •  9
    Suitable for those conducting research or teaching in philosophy, this title provides analyses of the continental tradition of philosophy from Kant. Placing continental philosophy within a historical context, it helps define what the continental tradition has been and where it is moving.
  •  73
    Ernst Cassirer
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  60
    Kant and the Exact Sciences
    Philosophical Review 104 (4): 587. 1995.
    This is a very important book. It has already become required reading for researchers on the relation between the exact sciences and Kant’s philosophy. The main theme is that Kant’s continuing program to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the science of his day is of crucial importance to understanding the development of his philosophical thought from its earliest precritical beginnings in the thesis of 1747, right through the highwater years of the critical philosophy, to hi…Read more
  •  231
    Carl Hempel introduced what he called "Craig's theorem" into the philosophy of science in a famous discussion of the "problem of theoretical terms." Beginning with Hempel's use of 'Craig's theorem," I shall bring out some of the key differences between Hempel's treatment of the "problem of theoretical terms" and Carnap's in order to illuminate the peculiar function of Wissenschaftslogik in Carnap's mature philosophy. Carnap's treatment, in particular, is fundamentally antimetaphysical—he aims to…Read more
  •  158
    Understanding space-time
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (1): 216-225. 2007.
  •  134
    The Re-evaluation of Logical Positivism
    Journal of Philosophy 88 (10): 505-519. 1991.
  •  136
    The Scientific Image by Bas C. van Fraassen (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (5): 274-283. 1982.
  •  82
    Transcendental Philosophy And Mathematical Physics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1): 29-43. 2003.
    his paper explores the relationship between Kant’s views on the metaphysical foundations of Newtonian mathematical physics and his more general transcendental philosophy articulated in the Critique of pure reason. I argue that the relationship between the two positions is very close indeed and, in particular, that taking this relationship seriously can shed new light on the structure of the transcendental deduction of the categories as expounded in the second edition of the Critique.Author Keywo…Read more
  •  26
  •  333
    Regulative and constitutive
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1): 73-102. 1992.
  •  16
    Does the materiality of a three-dimensional model have an effect on how this model operates in an exploratory way, how it prompts discovery of new mathematical results? Material mathematical models were produced and used during the second half of the nineteenth century, visualizing mathematical objects, such as curves and surfaces—and these were produced from a variety of materials: paper, cardboard, plaster, strings, wood. However, the question, whether their materiality influenced the status o…Read more