•  21
    [full article, abstract in English; abstract in Lithuanian] Fred Dretske motivates his denial of epistemic closure by way of the thought that the warrant for the premises of a valid argument need not transfer to the argument’s conclusion. The failure-of-transfer-of-warrant strategy has also been used by advocates of epistemic closure as a foil to Michael McKinsey’s argument against the compatibility of first person authority and semantic externalism, and also to illuminate, more generally, why c…Read more
  •  23
    The Rigidity of Proper Names
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33 189-200. 1991.
  •  16
    V*—Methodological Reflections on Two Kripkean Strategies
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95 (1): 67-82. 1995.
    Murali Ramachandran; V*—Methodological Reflections on Two Kripkean Strategies, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 95, Issue 1, 1 June 1995, Pages 6.
  •  16
    The Rigidity of Proper Names
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33 189-200. 1991.
  •  10
    How Believing Can Fail to Be Knowing
    Theoria 21 (2): 185-194. 2010.
    This paper puts forward necessary and suffficient conditions for knowing, and addresses Timothy Williamson's claims that knowledge is an un-analyzable mental state, and that any such analysis is futile. It is argued that such an account has explanatory motivation: it explains when belief fails to be knowledge.
  •  61
    Chisholm's Modal Paradox(es) and Counterpart Theory 50 Years On
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 1. forthcoming.
    Lewis’s [1968] counterpart theory (LCT for short), motivated by his modal realism, made its appearance within a year of Chisholm’s modal paradox [1967]. We are not modal realists, but we argue that a satisfactory resolution to the paradox calls for a counterpart-theoretic (CT-)semantics. We make our case by showing that the Chandler–Salmon strategy of denying the S4 axiom [◊◊ψ →◊ψ] is inadequate to resolve the paradox – we take on Salmon’s attempts to defend that strategy against objects from Le…Read more
  •  30
    Peptide drugs accelerate BMP‐2‐induced calvarial bone regeneration and stimulate osteoblast differentiation through mTORC1 signaling (review)
    with Yasutaka Sugamori, Setsuko Mise-Omata, Chizuko Maeda, Shigeki Aoki, Yasuhiko Tabata, Hisataka Yasuda, Nobuyuki Udagawa, Hiroshi Suzuki, Masashi Honma, and Kazuhiro Aoki
    Bioessays 38 (8): 717-725. 2016.
    Both W9 and OP3‐4 were known to bind the receptor activator of NF‐κB ligand (RANKL), inhibiting osteoclastogenesis. Recently, both peptides were shown to stimulate osteoblast differentiation; however, the mechanism underlying the activity of these peptides remains to be clarified. A primary osteoblast culture showed that rapamycin, an mTORC1 inhibitor, which was recently demonstrated to be an important serine/threonine kinase for bone formation, inhibited the peptide‐induced alkaline phosphatase…Read more
  •  65
    For a (revised) PCA-analysis
    Analysis 58 (1). 1998.
  •  35
    The Impossibility of Inverted Reasoners
    Acta Analytica 25 (4): 499-502. 2010.
    An ‘inverted’ reasoner is someone who finds the inferences we find easy, inversely difficult, and those that we find difficult, inversely easy. The notion was initially introduced by Christopher Cherniak in his book, Minimal Rationality, and appealed to by Stephen Stich in The Fragmentation of Reason. While a number of difficulties have been noted about what reasoning would amount to for such a reasoner, what has not been brought out in the literature is that such a reasoner is in fact logic…Read more
  •  59
    Methodological Reflections on Two Kripkean Strategies
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95. 1995.
    Aims. Saul Kripke’s (1977) argument defending Russell’s theory of (definite) descriptions (RTD) against the possible objection that Donnellan’s (1966) distinction between attributive and referential uses of descriptions marks a semantic ambiguity has been highly influential.1 Yet, as I hope you’ll be persuaded, Kripke’s line of reasoning— in particular, the ‘thought-experiment’ it involves—has not been duly explored. In section II, I argue that while Kripke’s argument does ward off a fairly ill-…Read more
  • (1) The table is covered with books. (2) There is exactly one table and it is covered with books.
  •  62
    One of Strawson's objections to Russell's theory of descriptions is that what are intuitively natural and correct utterances of sentences involving incomplete descriptions come out false by RTD. Russellians have responded, not by challenging Strawson's view that these uses are natural and correct, but by embellishing RTD to accommodate these uses. I pursue an alternative line of attack: I argue that there are circumstances in which "we" would find utterances of such sentences unnatural and impro…Read more
  •  63
    Unsuccessful Revisions of CCT
    Analysis 50 (3). 1990.
  •  286
    Anti-luminosity: Four unsuccessful strategies
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (4): 659-673. 2009.
    In Knowledge and Its Limits Timothy Williamson argues against the luminosity of phenomenal states in general by way of arguing against the luminosity of feeling cold, that is, against the view that if one feels cold, one is at least in a position to know that one does. In this paper I consider four strategies that emerge from his discussion, and argue that none succeeds.
  •  42
    Sense and schmidentity
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (157): 463-471. 1989.
  •  62
    Knowing by way of tracking and epistemic closure
    Analysis 75 (2): 217-223. 2015.
    Tracking accounts of knowledge were originally motivated by putative counter-examples to epistemic closure. But, as is now well known, these early accounts have many highly counterintuitive consequences. In this note, I motivate a tracking-based account which respects closure but which resolves many of the familiar problems for earlier tracking account along the way.
  •  152
    Contingent Identity in Counterpart Theory
    Analysis 50 (3): 163-166. 1990.
    A slight modification to the translation scheme for David Lewis's counterpart theory I put forward in 'An Alternative Translation Scheme for Counterpart Theory' (Analysis 49.3 (1989)) is proposed. The motivation for this change is that it makes for a more plausible account of contingent identity. In particular, contingent identity is accommodated without admitting the contingency of self-identity.
  •  257
    A counterfactual analysis of causation
    Mind 106 (422): 263-277. 1997.
    On David Lewis's original analysis of causation, c causes e only if c is linked to e by a chain of distinct events such that each event in the chain (counter-factually) depends on the former one. But this requirement precludes the possibility of late pre-emptive causation, of causation by fragile events, and of indeterministic causation. Lewis proposes three different strategies for accommodating these three kinds of cases, but none of these turn out to be satisfactory. I offer a single analysis…Read more
  •  140
    The KK-Principle, Margins for Error, and Safety
    Erkenntnis 76 (1): 121-136. 2012.
    This paper considers, and rejects, three strategies aimed at showing that the KK-principle fails even in most favourable circumstances (all emerging from Williamson’s Knowledge and its Limits ). The case against the final strategy provides positive grounds for thinking that the principle should hold good in such situations
  •  88
    Occasional identity: A tale of two approaches
    Analytic Philosophy 52 (3): 175-187. 2011.
  •  107
    Noordhof on probabilistic causation
    Mind 109 (434): 309-313. 2000.
    In a recent article, Paul Noordhof (1999) has put forward an intriguing account of causation intended to work under the assumption of indeterminism. I am going to present four problems for the account, three which challenge the necessity of the conditions he specifies, and one which challenges their joint-sufficiency.
  •  160
    How Believing Can Fail to Be Knowing
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 21 (2): 185-194. 2006.
    This paper defends a simple, externalist account of knowledge, incorporating familiar conditions mentioned in the literature, and responds to Timothy Williamson’s charge that any such analysis is futile because knowledge is semantically un-analyzable. The response, in short, is that even though such an account may not offer a reductive analysis of knowledge-by way of more basic, non-circular concepts-it still has an explanatory advantage over Williamson’s own position: it explains how belief can…Read more
  •  73
    Bach on Behalf of Russell
    Analysis 55 (4). 1995.
    An utterance of a sentence involving an incomplete (definite) description, ‘the F’, where the context—even taking the speaker’s intentions into account—does not determine a unique F, would be unintelligible. But an utterance (in the same context) of the corresponding Russellian paraphrase would not be unintelligible. So I urged in ‘A Strawsonian objection to Russell’s theory of descriptions’ (ANALYSIS 53, 1993, pp. 209-12). I compared an utterance of (1) The table is covered with books. with an …Read more
  •  213
    Williamson’s Argument Against the KK-Principle 157
    The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 1. 2005.
    Timothy Williamson (2000 ch. 5) presents a reductio against the luminosity of knowing, against, that is, the so-called KK-principle: if one knows p, then one knows (or is at least in a position to know) that one knows p.1 I do not endorse the principle, but I do not think Williamson’s argument succeeds in refuting it. My aim here is to show that the KK-principle is not the most obvious culprit behind the contradiction Williamson derives.
  •  47
    The Ambiguity Thesis Versus Kripke's Defence of Russell
    Mind and Language 11 (4): 371-387. 1996.
    In his influential paper 'Speaker's Reference and Semantic Reference', Kripke defends Russell's theory of descriptions against the charge that the existence of referential and attributive uses of descriptions reflects a semantic ambiguity. He presents a purely defensive argument to show that Russell's theory is not refuted by the referential usage and a number of methodological considerations which apparently tell in favour of Russell's unitary theory over an ambiguity theory. In this paper, I p…Read more
  •  51
    Sortal modal logic and counterpart theory
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (4). 1998.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  178
    Kripkean Counterpart Theory
    Polish Journal of Philosophy 2 (2): 89-106. 2008.
    David Lewis’s counterpart-theoretic semantics for quantified modal logic is motivated originally by worries about identifying objects across possible worlds; the counterpart relation is grounded more cautiously on comparative similarity. The possibility of contingent identity is an unsought -- and in some eyes, unwelcome -- consequence of this approach. In this paper I motivate a Kripkean counterpart theory by way of defending the prior, pre-theoretical, coherence of contingent directness. Conti…Read more
  •  226
    Descriptions and pressupositions: Strawson vs. Russell
    South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (3): 242-257. 2008.
    A Russellian theory of (definite) descriptions takes an utterance of the form ‘The F is G' to express a purely general proposition that affirms the existence of a (contextually) unique F: there is exactly one F [which is C] and it is G. Strawson, by contrast, takes the utterer to presuppose in some sense that there is exactly one salient F, but this is not part of what is asserted; rather, when the presupposition is not met the utterance simply fails to express a (true or false) proposition. A d…Read more