•  96
    Lógica, lenguajes formales y modalidad
    Andamios 20 (53): 45-60. 2023.
    This paper examines two alleged limitations in the use of formal languages: on the one hand, the trade-offs between expressive and inferential power, and on the other, the phenomenon of system imprisonment. After reconceptualizing the issue, we consider the role played by modality in the understanding of certain aspects of mathematical structures and argue for its centrality.
  •  120
    Resisting easy inferences
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (3): 729-735. 2021.
    Amie Thomasson has articulated a novel conception of ontological debates, defending an easy approach to ontological questions as part of the articulation of a deflationary metaphysical view (Thomasson, 2015). After raising some concerns to the approach, we sketch a neutralist alternative to her ontological framework, offering an even easier way of conducting ontological debates.
  •  73
    Putnam’s indispensability argument revisited, reassessed, revived
    Theoria : An International Journal for Theory, History and Fundations of Science 33 (2): 201-218. 2018.
    Crucial to Hilary Putnam’s realism in the philosophy of mathematics is to maintain the objectivity of mathematics without the commitment to the existence of mathematical objects. Putnam’s indispensability argument was devised as part of this conception. In this paper, I reconstruct and reassess Putnam’s argument for the indispensability of mathematics, and distinguish it from the more familiar, Quinean version of the argument. Although I argue that Putnam’s approach ultimately fails, I develop a…Read more
  •  86
    Scientific Theories, Models and the Semantic Approach
    with Krause Décio and Bueno Otávio
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 11 (2): 187-201. 2007.
    According to the semantic view, a theory is characterized by a class of models. In this paper, we examine critically some of the assumptions that underlie this approach. First, we recall that models are models of something. Thus we cannot leave completely aside the axiomatization of the theories under consideration, nor can we ignore the metamathematics used to elaborate these models, for changes in the metamathematics often impose restrictions on the resulting models. Second, based on a paralle…Read more
  •  85
    Empiricism, conservativeness, and quasi-truth
    Philosophy of Science 66 (3): 485. 1999.
    A first step is taken towards articulating a constructive empiricist philosophy of mathematics, thus extending van Fraassen's account to this domain. In order to do so, I adapt Field's nominalization program, making it compatible with an empiricist stance. Two changes are introduced: (a) Instead of taking conservativeness as the norm of mathematics, the empiricist countenances the weaker notion of quasi-truth (as formulated by da Costa and French), from which the formal properties of conservativ…Read more
  •  68
    Is there a zande logic?
    History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (1): 41-54. 1998.
    The issue of what consequences to draw from the existence of non-classical logical systems has been the subject of an interesting debate across a diversity of fields. In this paper the matter of alternative logics is considered with reference to a specific belief system and its propositions :the Azande are said to maintain beliefs about witchcraft which, when expressed propositionally, appear to be inconsistent. When the Azande have been presented with such inconsistencies, they either fail to s…Read more
  •  205
    We examine, from the partial structures perspective, two forms of applicability of mathematics: at the “bottom” level, the applicability of theoretical structures to the “appearances”, and at the “top” level, the applicability of mathematical to physical theories. We argue that, to accommodate these two forms of applicability, the partial structures approach needs to be extended to include a notion of “partial homomorphism”. As a case study, we present London's analysis of the superfluid behavio…Read more
  •  48
    In a recent debate, Eric Drexler and Richard Smalley have discussed the chemical and physical possibility of constructing molecular assemblers - devices that guide chemical reactions by placing, with atomic precision, reactive molecules. Drexler insisted on the mechanical feasibility of such assemblers, whereas Smalley resisted the idea that such devices could be chemically constructed, because we do not have the required control. Underlying the debate, there are differences regarding the approp…Read more
  •  38
    Belief Systems and Partial Spaces
    Foundations of Science 21 (1): 225-236. 2016.
    One important role of belief systems is to allow us to represent information about a certain domain of inquiry. This paper presents a formal framework to accommodate such information representation. Three cognitive models to represent information are discussed: conceptual spaces, state-spaces, and the problem spaces familiar from artificial intelligence. After indicating their weakness to deal with partial information, it is argued that an alternative, formulated in terms of partial structures, …Read more
  •  1
    What is Semantics? A Brief Note on a Huge Question
    with Newton da Costa and Jean-Yves Béziau
    Sorites 3 43-47. 1995.
    After mentioning the cogent connection between pure semantics and the particular set theoretical framework in which it is formulated, some issues regarding the conceptual status of semantics itself, as well as its relationship to logic, are concisely raised.
  •  12
    A evidência visual na ciência
    Scientiae Studia 9 (2): 267-290. 2011.
  •  3
    Omnibus Review (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2): 683-685. 1997.
    Reviewed Works:Chris Mortensen, Inconsistent Mathematics.Chris Mortensen, Peter Lavers, Category Theory.William James, Closed Set Sheaves and Their Categories.Chris Mortensen, Joshua Cole, Foundations: Provability, Truth and Sets.
  •  62
    Logical non-apriorism and the law of non-contradiction
    with Mark Colyvan
    In Graham Priest, Jc Beall & Bradley P. Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction : New Philosophical Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 156--175. 2004.
    A common response to those who question the Law of Non-Contradiction is that it is impossible to debate such a fundamental law of logic. The reasons for this response vary, but what seems to underlie them is the thought that there is a minimal set of logical resources without which rational debate is impossible. This chapter argues that this response is misguided. First, it defends non-apriorism in logic: the view that logic is in the same epistemic boat as other scientific theories. It then off…Read more
  •  100
    Styles of reasoning: A pluralist view
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (4): 657-665. 2012.
    Styles of reasoning are important devices to understand scientific practice. As I use the concept, a style of reasoning is a pattern of inferential relations that are used to select, interpret, and support evidence for scientific results. In this paper, I defend the view that there is a plurality of styles of reasoning: different domains of science often invoke different styles. I argue that this plurality is an important source of disunity in scientific practice, and it provides additional argu…Read more
  •  226
    Structural realism and the nature of structure
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (1): 111-139. 2015.
    Ontic Structural Realism is a version of realism about science according to which by positing the existence of structures, understood as basic components of reality, one can resolve central difficulties faced by standard versions of scientific realism. Structures are invoked to respond to two important challenges: one posed by the pessimist meta-induction and the other by the underdetermination of metaphysics by physics, which arises in non-relativistic quantum mechanics. We argue that difficult…Read more
  •  2
    Fundamental Truthmakers (edited book)
    with Javier Cumpa
    Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
  •  308
    Is Logic A Priori?
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 17 (1): 105-117. 2010.
  •  117
    Defeasible Reasoning + Partial Models: A Formal Framework for the Methodology of Research Programs (review)
    with Fernando Tohmé and Claudio Delrieux
    Foundations of Science 16 (1): 47-65. 2011.
    In this paper we show that any reasoning process in which conclusions can be both fallible and corrigible can be formalized in terms of two approaches: (i) syntactically, with the use of defeasible reasoning, according to which reasoning consists in the construction and assessment of arguments for and against a given claim, and (ii) semantically, with the use of partial structures, which allow for the representation of less than conclusive information. We are particularly interested in the forma…Read more
  •  59
    Realism and Anti-Realism about Science
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 5 (2): 145-167. 2015.
    Pyrrhonists provide a way of investigating the world in which conflicting views about a given topic are critically compared, assessed, and juxtaposed. Since Pyrrhonists are ultimately unable to decide between these views, they end up suspending judgment about the issues under examination. In this paper, I consider the question of whether Pyrrhonists can be realists or anti-realists about science, focusing, in particular, on contemporary philosophical discussions about it. Althoughprima faciethe …Read more
  •  625
    Yablo’s paradox is generated by the following (infinite) list of sentences (called the Yablo list): (s1) For all k > 1, sk is not true. (s2) For all k > 2, sk is not true. (s3) For all k > 3, sk is not true. . . . . . . . .
  •  225
    How to change it: modes of engagement, rationality, and stance voluntarism
    with Darrell Patrick Rowbottom
    Synthese 178 (1): 7-17. 2011.
    We have three goals in this paper. First, we outline an ontology of stance, and explain the role that modes of engagement and styles of reasoning play in the characterization of a stance. Second, we argue that we do enjoy a degree of control over the modes of engagement and styles of reasoning we adopt. Third, we contend that maximizing one’s prospects for change also maximizes one’s rationality
  •  26
    Putnam and the Indispensability of Mathematics
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 17 (2): 217. 2013.
    In this paper, I examine Putnam’s nuanced views in the philosophy of mathematics, distinguishing three proposals: modalism, quasi-empirical realism, and an indispensability view. I argue that, as he shifted through these views, Putnam aimed to preserve a semantic realist account of mathematics that avoids platonism. In the end, however, each of the proposals faces significant difficulties. A form of skepticism then emerges.
  •  690
    Visual evidence at the nanoscale
    Spontaneous Generations 2 (1): 132. 2008.
    Research at the nanoscale (10.
  •  1501
    Critical studies/book reviews 319
    with Jour A. Z. Z. O. U. N. I.
    Ask a philosopher what a proof is, and you’re likely to get an answer hii empaszng one or another regimentationl of that notion in terms of a finite sequence of formalized statements, each of which is either an axiom or is derived from an axiom by certain inference rules. (Wecan call this the formal conception of proof) Ask a mathematician what a proof is, and you will rbbl poay get a different-looking answer. Instead of stressing a partic- l uar regimented notion of proof, the answer the mathem…Read more
  •  118
    In this paper, we examine the concept of particle as it appears in quantum field theories, focusing on a puzzling situation regarding this concept. Although quantum ‘particles’ arise from fields, which form the basic ontology of QFT, and thus a certain concept of ‘particle’ is al- ways available, the properties ascribed to such ‘particles’ are not completely in agreement with the mathematical and logical description of such fields, which should be taken as individuals.