•  59
    Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism (edited book)
    with David Copp
    Oxford University Press. 2023.
    Morality seems to play a special role in human life distinct from conventional norms, like those of etiquette, or simple preferences based on subjective tastes. There are various theories of the foundations of morality, some of which treat morality as 'subjective' in an important way. 'Moral realism' is however a family of theories that take morality to have an objective factual basis, such that morality is not 'up to us' and is not 'under our control'. The contributions in this handbook explore…Read more
  •  214
    Function, Fitness, Flourishing
    In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism, Oxford University Press. pp. 264-292. 2023.
  •  140
    The Skills of Justice
    In Ellen Fridland & Pavase Carlotta (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Skills and Expertise, Rutledge. pp. 460-475. 2021.
  •  251
    Humility Is Not A Virtue
    In Mark Alfano, Michael Patrick Lynch & Alessandra Tanesini (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, Routledge. pp. 36-46. 2021.
  •  325
    The Axiology of Pain and Pleasure
    Journal of Value Inquiry 1-24. forthcoming.
    There is little more common in ethics than to think pain is intrinsically bad and pleasure is intrinsically good. A Humean-style error theory of the axiology of pain and pleasure is developed against these commonsense claims. We defend the thesis that the value of pain and pleasure is always contingent and only instrumental. We survey prominent theories of both intrinsic value and pain/pleasure, all of which assume that pain and pleasure are intrinsically valuable. We base our error theory o…Read more
  •  38
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  • Moral Metaphysics
    In Moral Reality, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The property of physical health is presented as a model for moral goodness, and a primer on being healthy follows. Healthiness is understood in terms of proper biological function. Conventionalism and relativism, two bugbears of moral realism, are discussed in relation to healthiness and found not to arouse suspicion about the reality of physical health. By analogy, these can be accommodated by moral realism. A discussion of the supervenience and reduction of goodness and health follows, and the…Read more
  • Moral Practicality
    In Moral Reality, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    It is absurd to be a motivational internalist about the property of health; there is no magnetism or queerness in tofu despite it being healthy, and the same tack should be taken with regard to the property of moral goodness. Intuitions behind internalism are found to be confused, and problems are discussed with regard to Hume and Williams on the one hand and Kant, Nagel, and Korsgaard on the other. Externalism is defended: each of us is not as responsive to goodness as we might be, and it is co…Read more
  • Moral Epistemology
    In Moral Reality, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The epistemology of medical practice is investigated and the notion of a skill is found to be central to learning about health. This is followed by a discussion of skills, based on the Greek understanding of a skill, as well as the Greek understanding of moral virtue as a skill. Virtue theory, deontology, and consequentialism are articulated by the structure of the epistemology. The argument from disagreement against moral realism is discussed and refuted. Finally, Aristotle's arguments against …Read more
  •  84
    On human rights * by James Griffin (review)
    Analysis 71 (1): 195-197. 2011.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  • Moral Language
    In Moral Reality, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    The semantics of “health” are discussed by way of Aquinas’ theory of analogical predication: “health” and “good” have the tripartite semantic structure in terms of a base use, causes, and signs. This tripartite structure is mapped back onto the discussion of virtue theory, deontology, and consequentialism. T. Horgan and M.Timmon's Moral Twin Earth problem for moral realism is discussed and found not to apply to the present theory. The syntax of biological function statements is explicated and fo…Read more
  • Introduction
    In Moral Reality, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    An extended transcendental argument for moral realism is given cast in terms of an “argument from error”. This is distinguished from an argument from moral phenomenology because the errors under consideration are those that go undetected despite our confidence of their existence. First person error is focused upon in particular as is the human condition in general. The argument establishes a presumption in favor of moral realism, not a conclusive proof. A theory of moral goodness is needed, and …Read more
  •  22
    Beyond the Basics of Emotions (review)
    Journal of Philosophy of Emotion 3 (1): 24-30. 2021.
    While emotions can play positive, contributory roles in our cognition and our lives, they frequently have the opposite effect. Michael Brady’s otherwise excellent introduction to the topic of emotion is unbalanced because he does not attend to harms emotions cause. The basic problem is that emotions have a normative aspect: they can be justified or unjustified and Brady does not attend to this. An example of this is Brady’s discussion of curiosity as the emotional motivation for knowledge. More …Read more
  •  342
    Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology
    Philosophies 7 (1): 2. 2021.
    Perhaps the most familiar understanding of “naturalism” derives from Quine, understanding it as a continuity of empirical theories of the world as described through the scientific method. So, it might be surprising that one of the most important naturalistic moral realists, Philippa Foot, rejects standard evolutionary biology in her justly lauded _Natural Goodness_. One of her main reasons for this is the true claim that humans can flourish (eudaimonia) without reproducing, which she claims cann…Read more
  •  690
    Virtues are excellences
    Ratio 35 (1): 49-60. 2021.
    One of the few points of unquestioned agreement in virtue theory is that the virtues are supposed to be excellences. The best way to understand the project of "virtue ethics" is to understand this claim as the idea that the virtues always yield correct moral action and, therefore, that we cannot be “too virtuous”. In other words, the virtues cannot be had in excess or “to a fault”. If we take this seriously, however, it yields the surprising conclusion that many traits which have been traditiona…Read more
  •  189
    Epistemic Temperance
    American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2): 109-124. 2019.
    The idea of epistemic temperance is introduced and explicated through a discussion of Plato's understanding of it. A variety of psychological and epistemic phenomena are presented which arise due to epistemic intemperance, or the inappropriate influence of conations on cognition. Two cases familiar to philosophers, self-deception and racial prejudice, are discussed as the result of epistemic intemperance though they are not typically seen as having a common cause. Finally, epistemic temperance i…Read more
  •  803
    The Character of the Hypocrite
    Journal of Philosophical Research 43 69-82. 2018.
    A distinction is made between acting hypocritically and the character trait of being a hypocrite. The former is understood as resulting from the employment of a double standard in order to obtain a wrongful advantage, while a particular problem with the latter is that hypocrites do not give trustworthy testimony.
  •  273
    Justice as a Self‐Regarding Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (1): 46-64. 2010.
  •  185
    Archimedeanism and Why Metaethics Matters
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4 283-302. 2009.
  •  625
    Tracking Eudaimonia
    Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 10 (2). 2018.
    A basic challenge to naturalistic moral realism is that, even if moral properties existed, there would be no way to naturalistically represent or track them. Here, the basic structure for a tracking account of moral epistemology is given in empirically respectable terms, based on a eudaimonist conception of morality. The goal is to show how this form of moral realism can be seen as consistent with the details of evolutionary biology as well as being amenable to the most current understanding of …Read more
  •  37
    Partially Re-Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  133
    Morality and Self-Interest (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The volume will act as a useful collection of scholarship by top figures, and as a resource and course book on an important topic.
  •  40
    Partially Re‐Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  182
    Virtue Epistemology and the Epistemology of Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23-43. 2000.
    The ancient Greeks almost universally accepted the thesis that virtues are skills. Skills have an underlying intellectual structure (logos), and having a particular skill entails understanding the relevant logos. possessing a general ability to diagnose and solve problems (phronesis). as well as having appropriate experience. Two implications of accepting this thesis for moral epistemology and epistemology in general are considered. Thinking of virtues as skills yields a viable virtue epistemolo…Read more
  •  103
    The harm of immorality
    Ratio 21 (3): 241-259. 2008.
    A central problem in moral theory is how it is to be defended against those who think that there is no harm in being immoral, and that immorality can be in one's self-interest, assuming the perpetrator is not caught and punished. The argument presented here defends the idea that being immoral prevents one from having self-respect. If it makes sense to think that one cannot be happy without self-respect, then the conclusion follows that one cannot be both immoral and happy. Immorality is harmful …Read more
  •  116
    Of Goodness and Healthiness: A Viable Moral Ontology
    Philosophical Studies 87 (3): 309-332. 1997.
  •  102
    Good To Be Bad?
    Think 14 (40): 51-55. 2015.