•  328
    Beneficence, Duty and Distance
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (4): 357-383. 2004.
    According to Peter Singer, virtually all of us would be forced by adequate reflection on our own convictions to embrace a radical conclusion about giving. The following principle, he says, is “surely undeniable” -- at least once we reflect on secure convictions concerning rescue, as in his famous case of the drowning toddler.
  •  297
    Actual Rule Utilitarianism
    Journal of Philosophy 106 (1): 5-28. 2009.
  •  134
    Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (3): 202-224. 1998.
    The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
  •  120
    Globalizing Justice: The Ethics of Poverty and Power
    Oxford University Press UK. 2010.
    Richard Miller presents a bold new program for international justice. He argues for new standards of responsible conduct by governments, firms, and individuals in developed countries, to govern trade, investment, environmental policy, and the use of force. He offers an urgently needed strategy for moving humanity toward genuine global co-operation.
  •  110
    Half-naturalized social kinds
    Philosophy of Science 67 (3): 652. 2000.
    We often legitimately ascribe reality both to social and to natural kinds. But the bases for these ascriptions are not entirely the same. In both cases, reality is typically determined by what characterizations of causal factors are indispensable to adequate explanation. Nonetheless, a psychological role as part of an identity that instances embrace is sometimes, distinctively, a condition for ascribing reality to a social kind. Although such assessments of reality can be construed as employing …Read more
  •  87
    The norms of reason
    Philosophical Review 104 (2): 205-245. 1995.
  •  86
    Methodological individualism and social explanation
    Philosophy of Science 45 (3): 387-414. 1978.
    Past criticisms to the contrary, methodological individualism in the social sciences is neither trivial nor obviously false. In the style of Weber's sociology, it restricts the ultimate explanatory repertoire of social science to agents' reasons for action. Although this restriction is not obviously false, it ought not to be accepted, at present, as a regulative principle. It excludes, as too far-fetched to merit investigation, certain hypotheses concerning the influence of objective interests o…Read more
  •  75
  •  73
    Relationships of Equality: A Camping Trip Revisited (review)
    The Journal of Ethics 14 (3-4): 231-253. 2010.
    G. A. Cohen incisively argued that our judgments of social justice should fit our convictions about how to interact with others in our personal lives. Ironically, the ordinary morality of cooperation invoked in his last book undermines his favored principle of equality, and supports John Rawls' reliance on a relevantly impartial choice promoting appropriate fundamental interests as a basis for distributive standards. His further objections to Rawls' account of distributive justice neglect the ro…Read more
  •  71
    Propensity: Popper or Peirce?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (2): 123-132. 1975.
  •  70
    Marx and Aristotle: A Kind of Consequentialism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (sup1): 323-352. 1981.
  •  62
    The Advancement of Realism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3): 637. 1995.
    Some of us think that the current consensus in the natural sciences is closer to the truth than it has ever been before. But for decades we have been told that important parts of this consensus are due to interactions of power, rhetoric and custom which have no tendency to promote truth in our own view. I think that the debunking of this debunking in The Advancement of Science is a devastating success, an awesome combination of erudition, philosophical insight and conceptual resourcefulness. But…Read more
  •  61
    Rawls, risk, and utilitarianism
    Philosophical Studies 28 (1). 1975.
  •  57
  •  48
    Wittgenstein in transition: A review of the philosophical grammar (review)
    Philosophical Review 86 (4): 520-544. 1977.
  •  48
    How Global Inequality Matters
    Journal of Social Philosophy 42 (1): 88-98. 2011.
  •  47
    In a wide-ranging inquiry Richard W. Miller provides new resources for coping with the most troubling types of moral conflict: disagreements in moral conviction, conflicting interests, and the tension between conscience and desires. Drawing on most fields in philosophy and the social sciences, including his previous work in the philosophy of science, he presents an account of our access to moral truth, and, within this framework, develops a theory of justice and an assessment of the role of mora…Read more
  •  47
    Solipsism in the Tractatus
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (1): 57-74. 1980.
  •  37
    Knowledge and Human Interests
    Philosophical Review 84 (2): 261. 1975.
  •  34
    Cosmopolitanism and Its Limits
    Theoria 51 (104): 38-53. 2004.
  •  31
    Democracy and Class Dictatorship: RICHARD W. MILLER
    Social Philosophy and Policy 3 (2): 59-76. 1986.
    Clearly, Marx thought he was promoting democratic values. In the Manifesto, the immediate goal of socialism is summed up as “to win the battle of democracy.” Marx sees the reduction of individuality as one of the greatest injuries done by a system in which most people buy and sell their labor power on terms over which they have little control. As they supervised translations and re-issues of the Manifesto, Marx and Engels singled out just one point as a major topic on which their view in 1848 ha…Read more
  •  28
    Truth in Beauty
    American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (4). 1979.
  •  26
    Too much inequality
    Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (1): 275-313. 2002.
    It used to seem so simple. In the old days , most political philosophers who were inclined to call themselves “egalitarian” thought that one or another version of this argument established at least the approximate truth about economic justice
  •  25
    Social Democracy and Free Enterprise
    Journal of Social Philosophy 50 (4): 597-619. 2019.
    Journal of Social Philosophy, EarlyView.