•  527
    Folk psychology as simulation
    Mind and Language 1 (2): 158-71. 1986.
  •  382
    Folk psychology as mental simulation
    The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2017.
    Mindreading (or folk psychology, Theory of Mind, mentalizing) is the capacity to represent and reason about others’ mental states. The Simulation Theory (ST) is one of the main approaches to mindreading. ST draws on the common-sense idea that we represent and reason about others’ mental states by putting ourselves in their shoes. More precisely, we typically arrive at representing others’ mental states by simulating their mental states in our own mind. This entry offers a detailed analysis of ST…Read more
  •  314
    Emotions and knowledge
    Journal of Philosophy 66 (July): 408-413. 1969.
  •  289
  •  208
    The Structure of Emotions argues that emotion concepts should have a much more important role in the social and behavioural sciences than they now enjoy, and shows that certain influential psychological theories of emotions overlook the explanatory power of our emotion concepts. Professor Gordon also outlines a new account of the nature of commonsense (or ‘folk’) psychology in general.
  •  195
    Sympathy, simulation, and the impartial spectator
    In L. May, Michael Friedman & A. Clark (eds.), Ethics, Mit Press. pp. 727-742. 1996.
  •  180
    An ascent routine (AR) allows a speaker to self-ascribe a given propositional attitude (PA) by redeploying the process that generates a corresponding lower level utterance. Thus, we may report on our beliefs about the weather by reporting (under certain constraints) on the weather. The chief criticism of my AR account of self-ascription, by Alvin Goldman and others, is that it covers few if any PA’s other than belief and offers no account of how we can attain reliability in identifying our attit…Read more
  •  152
    Beyond mindreading
    Philosophical Explorations 11 (3). 2008.
    I argue that there is no conflict between the simulation theory, once it is freed from certain constraints carried over from theory theory, and Gallagher's view that our primary and pervasive way of engaging with others rests on 'direct', non-mentalizing perception of the 'meanings' of others' facial expressions, gestures, and intentional actions
  •  135
    Judgmental emotions
    Analysis 34 (December): 40-48. 1973.
  •  133
    The Rationality of Emotion
    Philosophical Review 100 (2): 284. 1991.
    How should we understand the emotional rationality? This first part will explore two models of cognition and analogy strategies, test their intuition about the emotional desire. I distinguish between subjective and objective desire, then presents with a feeling from the "paradigm of drama" export semantics, here our emotional repertoire is acquired all the learned, and our emotions in the form of an object is fixed. It is pretty well in line with the general principles of rationality, especially…Read more
  •  78
    This paper supports the basic integrity of the folk psychological conception of consciousness and its importance in cognitive theorizing. Section 1 critically examines some proposed definitions of consciousness, and argues that the folk- psychological notion of phenomenal consciousness is not captured by various functional-relational definitions. Section 2 rebuts the arguments of several writers who challenge the very existence of phenomenal consciousness, or the coherence or tenability of the f…Read more
  •  77
    Fear
    Philosophical Review 89 (4): 560-578. 1980.
  •  65
    Simulation and reason explanation: The radical view
    Philosophical Topics 29 (1-2): 175-192. 2001.
    Alvin Goldman's early work in action theory and theory of knowledge was a major influence on my own thinking and writing about emotions. For that reason and others, it was a very happy moment in my professional life when I learned, in 1988, that in his presidential address to the Society for Philosophy and Psychology Goldman endorsed and defended the “simulation” theory I had put forward in a 1986 article. I discovered afterward that we share a strong conviction that empirical evidence is releva…Read more
  •  62
    The Aboutness of Emotions
    American Philosophical Quarterly 11 (1): 27-36. 1974.
    I attempt to show that when someone is, E.G., Angry about something, The events or states that conjointly are causing him to be angry conform to a certain structure, And that from the causal structure underlying his anger it is possible to 'read out' what he is angry about. In this respect, And even in some of the details of the structure, My analysis of being angry about something resembles the belief-Want analysis of intentional action. The chief elements of the causal structure I describe are…Read more
  •  52
    Sellars’s Ryleans Revisited
    ProtoSociology 14 102-114. 2000.
    Wilfrid Sellars's essay, "Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind," (1) introduced, although it did not exactly endorse, what many philosophers consider the first defense of functionalism in the philosophy of mind and the original "theory" theory of commonsense psychology
  •  52
    Reply to Stich and Nichols
    Mind and Language 7 (1-2): 87-97. 1992.
  •  48
    Emotion labelling and cognition
    Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 8 (2). 1978.
  •  47
    The Structure of Emotions
    Journal of Philosophy 86 (9): 493-504. 1989.
  •  42
    Empathy, simulation, and Pam
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (1): 37-37. 2001.
    The wealth of important and convergent evidence discussed in the target article contrasts with the poorly conceived theory put forward to explain it. The simulation theory does a better job of explaining how automatic “mirroring” mechanisms might work together with high-level cognitive processes. It also explains what the authors' PAM theory merely stipulates.
  •  42
    Socratic definitions and "moral neutrality"
    Journal of Philosophy 61 (15): 433-450. 1964.
  •  32
    Teleology and agency in speech production
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3): 525-525. 1986.
  •  30
    The prior question: Do human primates have a theory of mind?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1): 120-121. 1998.
    Given Heyes's construal of there is still no convincing evidence of theory of mind in human primates, much less nonhuman. Rather than making unfounded assumptions about what underlies human social competence, one should ask what mechanisms other primates have and then inquire whether more sophisticated elaborations of those might not account for much of human competence
  •  28
  •  27
    The Morality of Self-Interest (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 64 (3): 115-118. 1967.
  •  27
    Reply to Perner and Howes
    Mind and Language 7 (1-2): 98-103. 1992.