•  32
    Disjunctivism
    with John Hawthorne and Karson Kovakovich
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106 (1): 185-216. 2006.
  •  62
    Disjunctivism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1): 145-216. 2006.
    [John Hawthorne] We examine some well-known disjunctivist projects in the philosophy of perception, mainly in a critical vein. Our discussion is divided into four parts. Following some introductory remarks, we examine in part two the link between object-dependent contents and disjunctivism. In part three, we explore the disjunctivist's use of discriminability facts as a basis for understanding experience. In part four, we examine an interesting argument for disjunctivism that has been offered by…Read more
  •  23
    Reply to Comesaña
    Philosophical Studies 180 (10): 3231-3252. 2023.
  •  47
    Rationality and Higher-order Awareness
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (1): 78-98. 2022.
    It is argued that higher-order awareness is central to one type of everyday rationality. The author starts by specifying the target notion of rationality, contrasting it with other useful notions in the neighbourhood. It is then shown that the target notion relies on first-person awareness of the unfolding of cognition. This is used to explain the kernel of truth in epistemic conservatism, the structure of defeasibility, and the root motive behind the widely accepted distinction between rational…Read more
  •  54
    The Rational Mind
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    Scott Sturgeon presents an original account of mental states and their dynamics. He develops a detailed story of coarse- and fine-grained mental states, a novel perspective on how they fit together, an engaging theory of the rational transitions between them, and a fresh view of how formal methods can advance our understanding in this area. In doing so, he addresses a deep four-way divide in literature on epistemic rationality. Formal epistemology is done in specialized languages--often seeming …Read more
  • Confidence and Coarse-Grained Attitudes
    Oxford Studies in Epistemology 3. 2010.
  •  57
    The sharpest corner of the cutting edge of recent epistemology is to be found in Richard Pettigrew’s Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. In this fine book Pettigrew argues that a certain kind of accuracy-based value monism entails that rational credence manifests a host of features emphasized by anti-externalists in epistemology. Specifically, he demonstrates how a particular version of accuracy-based value monism—to be discussed at length below—when placed with some not implausible views about h…Read more
  •  71
    Pollock on defeasible reasons
    Philosophical Studies 169 (1): 105-118. 2014.
  •  443
    The epistemic basis of subjectivity
    Journal of Philosophy 91 (5): 221-35. 1994.
  •  188
    Visual experience
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98 (1): 179-200. 1998.
    I argue against a Disjunctive approach to visual experience. I then critique three 'common-factor' views: Qualia Theory, Intentionalism and Sense-Date Theory. The latter two are combined to form Intentional Trope Theory; and that view is defended
  •  103
    Humean chance: Five questions for David Lewis (review)
    Erkenntnis 49 (3): 321-335. 1998.
    David Lewis's approach to objective chance is doubly distinctive. On the one hand, Lewis uses an epistemic principle to disclose the nature of chance. One the other, Lewis conjoins realism about chance with a reductive Humean metaphysics. I aim to undermine both aspects of his view. Specifically, I argue that reductive Humeanism fails across the board, and I use my discussion of chance to explain why. I also argue Lewis's "best-systems" approach to chance fails his own criteria for a metaphysics…Read more
  •  44
    Conditional Belief and the Ramsey Test
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51 215-232. 2002.
    Consider the frame S believes that—. Fill it with a conditional, say If you eat an Apple, you'll drink a Coke. what makes the result true? More generally, what facts are marked by instances of S believes ? In a sense the answer is obious: beliefs are so marked. Yet that bromide leads directly to competing schools of thought. And the reason is simple. Common-sense thinks of belief two ways. Sometimes it sees it as a three-part affair. When so viewed either you believe, disbelieve, or suspend judg…Read more
  •  138
    Stalnaker on sensuous knowledge
    Philosophical Studies 137 (2). 2008.
    Robert Stalnaker has recently argued that a pair of natural thoughts are incompatible. One of them is the view that items of non-indexical factual knowledge rule out possibilities. The other is the view that knowing what sensuous experience is like involves non-indexical knowledge of its phenomenal character. I argue against Stalnaker’s take on things, elucidating along the way how our knowledge of what experience is like fits together with the natural idea that items of non-indexical factual kn…Read more
  •  21
    Modal infallibilism and basic truth
    In Fraser MacBride (ed.), Identity and Modality, Oxford University Press. pp. 40. 2006.
  •  155
    Belief, Reason & Logic
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64 89-100. 2009.
  •  129
    Truth in Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1): 99-108. 1991.
  •  181
    Pollock on defeasible reasons
    Philosophical Studies (1): 1-14. 2012.
  • Having Reason in Mind
    Dissertation, The University of Arizona. 1991.
    The project consists of a defense of the reductivist program generally and an application of the program to the theory of epistemic justification. ;Chapter One sets out the problem of reducing justification to other terms and defends the legitimacy of this problem against attacks by Quine in particular and supervenience theorists generally. Chapter Two is an explication and refutation of all possible theories which reduce justification-facts to facts about the reliability of cognitive processes.…Read more
  •  133
    Conceptual gaps and odd possibilities
    Mind 108 (430): 377-380. 1999.
    Scott Sturgeon has claimed to undermine the principal argument for Physicalism, in his words, the view that ’actuality is exhausted by physical reality’. In noting that actuality is exhausted by physical reality, the Physicalist is not claiming that all that there is in actuality are those things identified by physics. Rather the thought is that actuality is made up of all the things identified by physics and anything which is a compound of these things. So there are tables as well as their micr…Read more
  •  736
    The Tale of Bella and Creda
    Philosophers' Imprint 15. 2015.
    Some philosophers defend the view that epistemic agents believe by lending credence. Others defend the view that such agents lend credence by believing. It can strongly appear that the disagreement between them is notational, that nothing of substance turns on whether we are agents of one sort or the other. But that is demonstrably not so. Only one of these types of epistemic agent, at most, could manifest a human-like configuration of attitudes; and it turns out that not both types of agent are…Read more
  •  152
    Reflective disjunctivism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1). 2006.
  •  162
    _Matters of Mind_ examines the mind-body problem. It offers a chapter by chapter analysis of debates surrounding the problem, including visual experience, consciousness and the problem of Zombies and Ghosts. It will prove invaluable for those interested in epistemology, philosophy of mind and cognitive science
  •  10
    Foley on causation and rationality
    Analysis 46 (4): 62-64. 1986.
  •  42
    The roots of reductionism
    In Carl Gillett & Barry Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents, Cambridge University Press. 2001.
  •  51
    II—Scott Sturgeon: Reflective Disjunctivism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1): 185-216. 2006.
  •  109
    Disjunctivism about visual experience
    In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 112--143. 2008.