-
219Must We Vaccinate the Most Vulnerable? Efficiency, Priority, and Equality in the Distribution of VaccinesJournal of Applied Philosophy 39 (4): 682-697. 2022.In this article, we aim to map out the complexities which characterise debates about the ethics of vaccine distribution, particularly those surrounding the distribution of the COVID-19 vaccine. In doing so, we distinguish three general principles which might be used to distribute goods and two ambiguities in how one might wish to spell them out. We then argue that we can understand actual debates around the COVID-19 vaccine – including those over prioritising vaccinating the most vulnerable – as…Read more
-
178Expert testimony and epistemological free-riding: The mmr controversyPhilosophical Quarterly 61 (244): 496-517. 2011.Using the controversy over the MMR vaccine, I consider the reasons why non-experts should defer to experts, and I sketch a model for understanding cases where they fail to defer. I first suggest that an intuitively plausible model of the expert/non-expert relationship is complicated by shifting epistemic standards. One possible moderate response to this challenge, based on a more complex notion of non-experts' relationship with experts, seems unappealing as an account of the MMR controversy. A m…Read more
-
162Costa, cancer and coronavirus: contractualism as a guide to the ethics of lockdownJournal of Medical Ethics 48 (9): 643-650. 2022.Lockdown measures in response to the COVID-19 pandemic involve placing huge burdens on some members of society for the sake of benefiting other members of society. How should we decide when these policies are permissible? Many writers propose we should address this question using cost-benefit analysis, a broadly consequentialist approach. We argue for an alternative non-consequentialist approach, grounded in contractualist moral theorising. The first section sets up key issues in the ethics of l…Read more
-
128Security, Knowledge and Well-beingJournal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1): 68-91. 2011.This paper investigates whether being “physically insecure” (being at risk of not continuing to meet one's physical needs in the future) should be thought of as a constituent of current wellbeing. In §1, it is argued that we cannot understand the value of security in terms of “freedom from fear”. In §2, it is argued that the reliablist approach to epistemology can help us to construct an account of why physical security is valuable, by relating security to the conditions of agency for practicall…Read more
-
126In Defence of Bad Science and Irrational Policies: an Alternative Account of the Precautionary PrincipleEthical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (1): 3-18. 2010.In the first part of the paper, three objections to the precautionary principle are outlined: the principle requires some account of how to balance risks of significant harms; the principle focuses on action and ignores the costs of inaction; and the principle threatens epistemic anarchy. I argue that these objections may overlook two distinctive features of precautionary thought: a suspicion of the value of “full scientific certainty”; and a desire to distinguish environmental doings from allow…Read more
-
125Inductive risk and the contexts of communicationSynthese 192 (1): 79-96. 2015.In recent years, the argument from inductive risk against value free science has enjoyed a revival. This paper investigates and clarifies this argument through means of a case-study: neonicitinoid research. Sect. 1 argues that the argument from inductive risk is best conceptualised as a claim about scientists’ communicative obligations. Sect. 2 then shows why this argument is inapplicable to “public communication”. Sect. 3 outlines non-epistemic reasons why non-epistemic values should not play a…Read more
-
104The example of the IPCC does not vindicate the Value Free Ideal: a reply to Gregor BetzEuropean Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (1): 1-13. 2015.In a recent paper, Gregor Betz has defended the value-free ideal: “the justification of scientific findings should not be based on non-epistemic values”against the methodological critique, by reference to the work of the International Panel on Climate Change . This paper argues that Betz’s defence is unsuccessful. First, Betz’s argument is sketched, and it is shown that the IPCC does not avoid the need to “translate” claims. In Section 2, it is argued that Betz mischaracterises the force of the …Read more
-
91Why 'health' is not a central category for public health policyJournal of Applied Philosophy 26 (2): 129-143. 2009.We normally think that public health policy is an important political activity. In turn, we normally understand the value of public health policy in terms of the promotion of health or some health-related good (such as opportunity for health), on the basis of the assumption that health is an important constituent or determinant of wellbeing. In this paper, I argue that the assumption that the value of public health policy should be understood in terms of health leads us to overlook important ben…Read more
-
80The Ethics of Lockdown: Communication, Consequences, and the Separateness of PersonsKennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 30 (3): 265-289. 2020.In many countries and regions across the world, the initial response to the massive health risks posed by COVID-19 has been the institution of lockdown measures. Although they vary from place to place, these measures all involve trade-offs between ethical goods and imperatives, imposing significant restrictions on central human capabilities—including citizens’ ability to work, socialize, exercise democratic rights, and access education—in the name of protecting population health. As such, it see…Read more
-
77Efficiency, responsibility and disability: Philosophical lessons from the savings argument for pre-natal diagnosisPolitics, Philosophy and Economics 14 (1): 1470594-13505412. 2015.Pre-natal-diagnosis technologies allow parents to discover whether their child is likely to suffer from serious disability. One argument for state funding of access to such technologies is that doing so would be “cost-effective”, in the sense that the expected financial costs of such a programme would be outweighed by expected “benefits”, stemming from the births of fewer children with serious disabilities. This argument is extremely controversial. This paper argues that the argument may not be …Read more
-
66Titanic Ethics, Pirate Ethics, Bio-Ethics: Essay Review of Paul, Miller and Paul, eds., Bioethics (review)Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, Series C 35 (21): 177-184. 2004.
-
56Risk, Contractualism, and Rose's "Prevention Paradox"Social Theory and Practice 40 (1): 28-50. 2014.Geoffrey Rose’s prevention paradox points to a tension between two prima facie plausible moral principles: that we should save the greater number and that weshould save the most at risk. This paper argues that a novel moral theory, ex-ante contractualism, captures our intuitions in many prevention paradox cases, regardless of our interpretation of probability claims. However, it goes on to show that it might be impossible to square ex-ante contractualism with all of our moral intuitions. It conc…Read more
-
54From Social Values to P-Values: The Social Epistemology of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate ChangeJournal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2): 157-171. 2017.In this article I ask two questions prompted by the phenomenon of ‘politically patterned’ climate change denial. First, can an individual's political commitments provide her with good reasons not to defer to cognitive experts’ testimony? Building on work in philosophy of science on inductive risk, I argue they can. Second, can an individual's political commitments provide her with good reasons not to defer to the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change's testimony? I argue that they cannot, be…Read more
-
46Science, truth and dictatorship: Wishful thinking or wishful speaking?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 78 64-72. 2019.
-
35Three Worries About Three Arguments for Research ExceptionalismAmerican Journal of Bioethics 10 (8): 67-69. 2010.This Article does not have an abstract
-
35The Politics of Certainty: The Precautionary Principle, Inductive Risk and Procedural FairnessEthics, Policy and Environment 22 (1): 21-33. 2019.This paper re-interprets the precautionary principle as a ‘social epistemic rule’. First, it argues that sometimes policy-makers should act on claims which have not been scientifically established....
-
31Alex Broadbent philosophy of epidemiologyBritish Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (3): 707-711. 2015.
-
29Titanic ethics, pirate ethics, bioethicsStudies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35 (1): 177-184. 2004.
-
28Objectivity in ScienceCambridge University Press. 2021.Objectivity is a key concept both in how we talk about science in everyday life and in the philosophy of science. This Element explores various ways in which recent philosophers of science have thought about the nature, value and achievability of objectivity. The first section explains the general trend in recent philosophy of science away from a notion of objectivity as a 'view from nowhere' to a focus on the relationship between objectivity and trust. Section 2 discusses the relationship betwe…Read more
-
27This paper uses the case-study of controversy over the MMT vaccine to suggest that non-expert audiences might have a fairness-based "political" obligation to defer to expert scientific consensus. The first part of the paper notes various reasons why it is implausible to argue that non-experts are epistemically obliged to defer to the consensus. The second draws on the literature on vaccination ethics more generally to argue for the alternative political obligation to defer. The third section con…Read more
-
27How to take deontological concerns seriously in risk-cost-benefit analysis: a re-interpretation of the precautionary principleJournal of Medical Ethics 33 (4): 221-224. 2007.In this paper the coherence of the precautionary principle as a guide to public health policy is considered. Two conditions that any account of the principle must meet are outlined, a condition of practicality and a condition of publicity. The principle is interpreted in terms of a tripartite division of the outcomes of action . Such a division of outcomes can be justified on either “consequentialist” or “deontological” grounds. In the second half of the paper, it is argued that the precautionar…Read more
-
25Risk, Contractualism, and Rose'sSocial Theory and Practice 40 (1): 28-50. 2014.Geoffrey Rose’s prevention paradox points to a tension between two prima facie plausible moral principles: that we should save the greater number and that weshould save the most at risk. This paper argues that a novel moral theory, ex-ante contractualism, captures our intuitions in many prevention paradox cases, regardless of our interpretation of probability claims. However, it goes on to show that it might be impossible to square ex-ante contractualism with all of our moral intuitions. It conc…Read more
-
22Risk and PrecautionPublic Health Ethics: Key Concepts and Issues in Policy and Practice 67--84. forthcoming.
-
21Should We Punish Responsible Drinkers? Prevention, Paternalism and Categorization in Public HealthPublic Health Ethics 11 (1): 35-44. 2018.Many public debates over policies aimed at curbing alcohol consumption start from an assumption that policies should not affect ‘responsible’ drinkers. In this article, I examine this normative claim, which I call prudentialism. In the first part of the article, I argue that prudentialism is both a demanding and distinctive doctrine, which philosophers should consider seriously. In the middle sections, I examine the relationship between prudentialism and two familiar topics in public health ethi…Read more
-
20Philosophy and the Precautionary Principle: Science, Evidence, and Environmental Policy Daniel Steel, 2014 Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 266 pp., £60/$95 (review)Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (2): 217-218. 2016.
-
19Patient Preference Predictors, Apt Categorization, and Respect for AutonomyJournal of Medicine and Philosophy 39 (2): 169-177. 2014.In this paper, I set out two ethical complications for Rid and Wendler’s proposal that a “Patient Preference Predictor” (PPP) should be used to aid decision making about incapacitated patients’ care. Both of these worries concern how a PPP might categorize patients. In the first section of the paper, I set out some general considerations about the “ethics of apt categorization” within stratified medicine and show how these challenge certain PPPs. In the second section, I argue for a more specifi…Read more
-
16“First, Do No Harm”?Social Theory and Practice 48 (3): 525-551. 2022.Screening for asymptomatic disease is a routine aspect of contemporary public health practice. However, it is also controversial, because it leads to overdiagnosis and overtreatment, with many arguing that programmes are “ineffective,” i.e., the “costs” outweigh the “benefits.” This paper explores a more fundamental objection to screening programmes: that, even if they are effective, they are ethically impermissible because they breach the principle of non-maleficence. In so doing, it suggests a…Read more
-
Cambridge UniversityDepartment of History and Philosophy of Science, Pemproke CollegeSenior Lecturer
Areas of Specialization
Value Theory |
Science, Logic, and Mathematics |