•  6
    Three Nordic Neo-Aristotelians and the First Doorkeeper of Logic
    Studia Neoaristotelica 19 (1): 3-106. 2022.
    I discuss the views on logic held by three early Nordic neo-Aristotelians — the Swedes Johannes Canuti Lenaeus (1573–1669) and Johannes Rudbeckius (1581–1646), and the Dane Caspar Bartholin (1585–1629). They all studied in Wittenberg (enrolled respectively in 1597, 1601, and 1604) and were exponents of protestant (Lutheran) scholasticism. The works I utilize are Janitores logici bini (1607) and Enchiridion logicum (1608) by Bartholin; Logica (1625) and Controversiae logices (1629) by Rudbeckius;…Read more
  •  5
    Intentionala objekt: några logiska synpunkter
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 48 (3-4): 304-313. 2013.
  •  6
    On Modal Logics, IF Logic, and IF Modal Logic
    with Merlijn Sevenster
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 481-501. 1998.
  •  3
    Modal logic of time division
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 363-387. 1998.
  •  3
    Decidability of IF Modal Logic of Perfect Recall
    with T. Hyttinen
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 111-131. 1998.
  •  2
    On IF Modal Logic and its Expressive Power
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 475-498. 1998.
  • A Formal Framework for Future Contingents
    Filosofiska Notiser 7 (1): 79-136. 2020.
    In this article, I present a formal semantic framework that renders explicit how to reconcile the condition that a proposition about a contingent future event is true at a moment t0 with the idea that at t0, this proposition is ‘truth-maker indeterminate’: a state of affairs making it true will obtain later on, though no such state of affairs obtains at t0. The semantics I formulate employs ‘open temporal models’. They represent the passage of time by a specific component termed time-resource, w…Read more
  • I argue that the semantics of sentences expressing future contingent propositions is best viewed as being based on a clear distinction between a time at which a proposition is true and a time at which a state of affairs that makes it true gets actualized. That a prediction is true here and now means that its truth-maker gets actualized later. This is not to say that if a contingent proposition p concerning the future is true at t, it acquires the truth-value true at t only retrospectively, at a …Read more
  •  36
    This book develops a novel generalization of possible world semantics, called ‘world line semantics’, which recognizes worlds and links between world-bound objects (world lines) as mutually independent aspects of modal semantics. Addressing a wide range of questions vital for contemporary debates in logic and philosophy of language and offering new tools for theoretical linguistics and knowledge representation, the book proposes a radically new paradigm in modal semantics. This framework is moti…Read more
  •  22
    Johannes Rudbeckius’s View on the Nature of Logic
    Studia Neoaristotelica 15 (2): 135-215. 2018.
    Johannes Rudbeckius, one of Sweden’s most influential figures in theology, pedagogy, and church-state relations in the 17th century, published two books on logic: Logica ex optimis et præstantissimis autoribus collecta & conscripta and Controversiæ logices vel potius earum epitome. In this paper, I present and critically discuss Rudbeckius’s view on the nature of logic as it can be reconstructed from these two works. This requires, in particular, identifying the larger intellectual framework wit…Read more
  •  14
    Modal logic of time division
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 363-387. 1998.
  •  10
    On Modal Logics, IF Logic, and IF Modal Logic
    with Merlijn Sevenster
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 481-501. 1998.
  •  9
    On IF Modal Logic and its Expressive Power
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 475-498. 1998.
  •  7
    Decidability of IF Modal Logic of Perfect Recall
    with T. Hyttinen
    In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Csli Publications. pp. 111-131. 1998.
  •  30
    Johannes Rudbeckius’s Conclusio Collegii Logici
    Studia Neoaristotelica 14 (2): 189-208. 2017.
    Propono hic conversionem in linguam Anglicam conclusionis Collegii Logici, anno 1608–1609 semestri studiorum spatio hiberno a Johanne Rudbeckio Wittenbergæ habiti. Hic commentarius prooemium in conversionem est. Rudbeckius primus Suecus erat, qui librum didacticum de logica publicavit. Maiorem partem libri iam anno 1606 scripserat, cum Mathesis Professor Upsaliensis esset, sed Logica ex optimis et præstantissimis autoribus collecta & conscripta non ante annum 1625 edita sit. Cum Johanne Canuti L…Read more
  •  34
    IF Modal Logic and Classical Negation
    Studia Logica 102 (1): 41-66. 2014.
    The present paper provides novel results on the model theory of Independence friendly modal logic. We concentrate on its particularly well-behaved fragment that was introduced in Tulenheimo and Sevenster (Advances in Modal Logic, 2006). Here we refer to this fragment as ‘Simple IF modal logic’ (IFML s ). A model-theoretic criterion is presented which serves to tell when a formula of IFML s is not equivalent to any formula of basic modal logic (ML). We generalize the notion of bisimulation famili…Read more
  •  67
    This volume includes a target paper, taking up the challenge to revive, within a modern (formal) framework, a medieval solution to the Liar Paradox which did ...
  •  22
    Sur les « opérateurs rétrogrades »
    Philosophia Scientiae 8 145-160. 2004.
    Une logique d’« opérateurs rétrogrades » (OR) est définie en utilisant des jeux sémantiques, joués sur des modèles à deux dimensions, l’une pour le temps, l’autre pour les scénarios épistémiques. On démontre que l’expressivité de OR est plus grande que celle de la logique de base des attitudes propositionnelles (AL). De plus, on établit que les pouvoirs expressifs de OR et la logique hybride AL + ↓ + @ coïncident. L’intérêt théorique général des opérateurs rétrogrades est brièvement discuté.
  •  26
    Classical Negation and Game-Theoretical Semantics
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (4): 469-498. 2014.
    Typical applications of Hintikka’s game-theoretical semantics give rise to semantic attributes—truth, falsity—expressible in the $\Sigma^{1}_{1}$-fragment of second-order logic. Actually a much more general notion of semantic attribute is motivated by strategic considerations. When identifying such a generalization, the notion of classical negation plays a crucial role. We study two languages, $L_{1}$ and $L_{2}$, in both of which two negation signs are available: $\rightharpoondown $ and $\sim$…Read more
  •  43
    Partially ordered connectives and monadic monotone strict np
    with Lauri Hella and Merlijn Sevenster
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 17 (3): 323-344. 2008.
    Motivated by constraint satisfaction problems, Feder and Vardi (SIAM Journal of Computing, 28, 57–104, 1998) set out to search for fragments of satisfying the dichotomy property: every problem definable in is either in P or else NP-complete. Feder and Vardi considered in this connection two logics, strict NP (or SNP) and monadic, monotone, strict NP without inequalities (or MMSNP). The former consists of formulas of the form , where is a quantifier-free formula in a relational vocabulary; and th…Read more
  •  71
    Negation and Temporal Ontology
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (1): 101-114. 2011.
    G. H. von Wright proposed that a temporal interval exemplifies a real contradiction if at least one part of any division of this interval involves the presence of contradictorily related (though non-simultaneous) states. In connection with intervals, two negations must be discerned: 'does not hold at an interval' and 'fails throughout an interval'. Von Wright did not distinguish the two. As a consequence, he made a mistake in indicating how to use his logical symbolism to express the notion of r…Read more
  •  98
    Between de dicto and de re: De objecto attitudes
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (245): 828-838. 2011.
    Hintikka's second generation epistemic logic introduces a syntactic device allowing to express independence relations between certain logical constants. De re knowledge attributions can be reformulated in terms of quantifier independence, but the reformulation does not extend to non-factive attitudes like belief. There, formulae with independent quantifiers serve to express a new type of attitude, intermediate between de dicto and de re, called ‘de objecto’: in each possible world compatible wit…Read more
  •  75
    The two faces of compatibility with justified beliefs
    Synthese 193 (1): 15-30. 2016.
    When discussing knowledge, two relations are of interest: justified doxastic accessibility \ , she is in \ ) and justification equivalence \ exactly the same justified beliefs that she has in \ ). Speaking of compatibility with the agent’s justified beliefs is potentially ambiguous: either of the two relations \ or \ can be meant. I discuss the possibility of identifying the relation of epistemic accessibility \ , she is in \ ) with the union of \ and \ . Neither Gettier’s examples nor the ‘fake…Read more
  •  57
    Hybrid logic meets if modal logic
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18 (4): 559-591. 2009.
    The hybrid logic and the independence friendly modal logic IFML are compared for their expressive powers. We introduce a logic IFML c having a non-standard syntax and a compositional semantics; in terms of this logic a syntactic fragment of IFML is singled out, denoted IFML c . (In the Appendix it is shown that the game-theoretic semantics of IFML c coincides with the compositional semantics of IFML c .) The hybrid logic is proven to be strictly more expressive than IFML c . By contrast, and the…Read more
  •  53
    This volume presents mathematical game theory as an interface between logic and philosophy.
  •  68
    Remarks on Individuals in Modal Contexts
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 250 (4): 383-394. 2009.
  •  45
    Worlds, times and selves revisited
    Synthese 193 (11): 3713-3725. 2016.
    In Prior’s tense-logical analysis, we can avoid mentioning instants in our language by construing them as propositions of a special kind. Instead of qualifying instants by predicates, we may qualify propositions by modalities. Prior shows that by changing the informal interpretation of our modal-like language, we can similarly attempt to avoid ontological commitments to worlds and even to selves and other bona fide individuals. As he notes, the paraphrasing strategy works too generally to be of …Read more
  •  47
    Independence friendly logic
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010.
  •  75
    From games to dialogues and back
    with Shahid Rahman
    In Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.), Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy, Springer Verlag. pp. 153--208. 2009.