•  4
    Mass Immunisation Programmes: Some Philosophical Issues
    Bioethics 12 (2): 125-149. 2002.
    Most countries promote mass immunisation programmes. The varying policy details raise a raft of philosophical issues. I have two broad aims in this paper. First, I hope to begin to remedy a rather curious philosophical neglect of immunisation. With this in mind, I take a broad approach to the topic hoping to introduce rather than settle a range of philosophical issues. My second aim has two aspects: I argue that the states should have pro‐immunisation policies, and I advance a view on the subseq…Read more
  •  158
    Lawyers, Ethics, and To Kill a Mockingbird
    Philosophy and Literature 25 (1): 127-141. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 25.1 (2001) 127-141 [Access article in PDF] Lawyers, Ethics, and To Kill a Mockingbird Tim Dare I Lawyers are widely thought to be callous, self-serving, devious, and indifferent to justice, truth, and the public good. The law profession could do with a hero, and some think Atticus Finch of Harper Lee's To Kill a Mockingbird fits the bill. 1 Claudia Carver, for instance, urging lawyers to adopt Atticus as a …Read more
  •  29
    The commentaries
    with Samuel Gorovitz and Michael Loughlin
    Health Care Analysis 2 (3): 190-199. 1994.
  •  14
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Alice Woolley, Gregory J. Cooper, and Daniel Markovits
    Legal Ethics 13 (2): 231-269. 2010.
  •  32
    The Philosophical Use and Misuse of Science
    Metaphilosophy 48 (4): 449-466. 2017.
    Science is our best way of finding out about the natural world, and philosophers who write about that world ought to be sensitive to the claims of our best science. There are obstacles, however, to outsiders using science well. We think philosophers are prone to misuse science: to give undue weight to results that are untested; to highlight favorable and ignore unfavorable data; to give illegitimate weight to the authority of science; to leap from scientific premises to philosophical conclusions…Read more
  •  23
    Virtue Ethics, Lawyers and Harper Lee's To Kill a Mockingbird
    Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 19 (1-2): 81-100. 2007.
    Atticus Finch, the lawyer-hero of Harper Lee's To Kill a Mockingbird, played by Gregory Peck in the classic 1962 film version, has been adopted as an exemplar by advocates of a virtue ethics approach to legal ethics. When Atticus condones a departure from the rules of law in order to spare Boo Radley a trial, these theorists argue, he displays practical wisdom, or phronesis, and shows that the good lawyer gives priority to judgement and character over rules and principles. Yet Atticus can be und…Read more
  •  17
    What Are Human Rights?
    Philosophy Now 118 14-17. 2017.
  •  11
    There is a widespread perception that even when lawyers are acting squarely within their roles, being good lawyers, they display the vices of dishonesty and deviousness. At the heart of the perception is the so called standard conception of the lawyer's role according to which lawyers owe special duties to their clients which render permissible, or even mandatory, acts that would otherwise count as morally impermissible. Many have concluded that the standard conception should be set aside. This …Read more
  •  21
    3. The Ethics in Legal Ethics
    Legal Ethics 13 (2): 182. 2010.
  •  1
    Raz and Legal Positivism
    Eidos: The Canadian Graduate Journal of Philosophy 8
  •  45
    Lawyers, ethics, and
    Philosophy and Literature 25 (1): 127-141. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 25.1 (2001) 127-141 [Access article in PDF] Lawyers, Ethics, and To Kill a Mockingbird Tim Dare I Lawyers are widely thought to be callous, self-serving, devious, and indifferent to justice, truth, and the public good. The law profession could do with a hero, and some think Atticus Finch of Harper Lee's To Kill a Mockingbird fits the bill. 1 Claudia Carver, for instance, urging lawyers to adopt Atticus as a …Read more
  •  9
    Professional ethics and personal integrity (edited book)
    with W. Bradley Wendel
    Cambridge Scholars Press. 2010.
    Professional roles are often thought to bring role-specific permissions and obligation, which may allow or require role-occupants to do things they would not be permitted or required to do outside their roles, and which as individuals they would rather not do. This feature of professional roles appears to bring them into conflict both with 'ordinary' or non-role morality, and with personal integrity which is often thought to demand some form of personal endorsement of one's conduct. How are we t…Read more
  •  30
    Although our moral lives would be unrecognisable without them, roles have received little attention from analytic moral philosophers. Roles are central to our lives and to our engagement with one another, and should be analysed in connection with our core notions of ethics such as virtue, reason, and obligation. This volume aims to redress the neglect of role ethics by confronting the tensions between conceptions of impartial morality and role obligations in the history of analytic philosophy an…Read more
  •  28
    ‘Intergenerational Justice’, by Janna Thompson
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2): 407-410. 2012.
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 90, Issue 2, Page 407-410, June 2012
  •  69
    Most countries promote mass immunisation programmes. The varying policy details raise a raft of philosophical issues. I have two broad aims in this paper. First, I hope to begin to remedy a rather curious philosophical neglect of immunisation. With this in mind, I take a broad approach to the topic hoping to introduce rather than settle a range of philosophical issues. My second aim has two aspects: I argue that the states should have pro-immunisation policies, and I advance a view of the subseq…Read more
  •  684
    To have the burden of proof is to be rationally required to argue for or provide evidence for your position. To have a heavier burden than an opponent is to be rationally required to provide better evidence or better arguments than they are required to provide. Many commentators suggest that differential or uneven distribution of the burden of proof is ubiquitous. In reasoned discourse, the idea goes, it is almost always the case that one party must prove the claim at issue to prevent the opposi…Read more
  •  31
    Political Theory for Mortals (review)
    Dialogue 39 (1): 189-191. 2000.
    John Seery begins his book with a stirring condemnation of current political theory. He was attracted to the discipline, he reports, because it promised more than a life of idle speculation and disinterested contemplation. Though ensconced in academe, political theorists "at least have one foot out the door." However, political theory has lost its connection to the real world. Much current writing is predictable and formulaic, too much time is spent scoring points, establishing professional auth…Read more
  •  20
    Paternalism in practice: informing patients about expensive unsubsidised drugs
    with M. Findlay, P. Browett, K. Amies, and S. Anderson
    Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (5): 260-264. 2010.
    Recent research conducted in Australia shows that many oncologists withhold information about expensive unfunded drugs in what the authors of the study suggest is unacceptable medical paternalism. Surprised by the Australian results, we ran a version of the study in New Zealand and received very different results. While the percentages of clinicians who would prescribe the drugs described in the scenarios were very similar (73–99% in New Zealand and 72–94% in Australia depending on the scenario)…Read more
  •  101
    This paper argues that significant aspects of the vaccination debate are ‘deep’ in a sense described by Robert Fogelin and others. Some commentators have suggested that such disagreements warrant rather threatening responses. I argue that appreciating that a disagreement is deep might have positive implications, changing our moral assessment of individuals and their decisions, shedding light on the limits of the obligation to give and respond to arguments in cases of moral disagreement, and prov…Read more
  •  18
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 104 (415): 654-658. 1995.
  •  55
    Ronald Dworkin argues that disagreement in hard cases is ‘theoretical’ rather than empirical and of central importance to our understanding of law, showing ‘plain fact’ theories such as H. L. A. Hart’s sophisticated legal positivism to be false. The argument from theoretical disagreement targets positivism’s commitment to idea that the criteria a norm must meet to be valid in a given jurisdiction are constituted by a practice of convergent behavior by legal officials. The ATD suggests that in ha…Read more
  •  14
    Addressing Child Maltreatment in New Zealand: Is Poverty Reduction Enough?
    with Rhema Vaithianathan and Irene De Haan
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 46 (9): 989-994. 2014.
    Jonathan Boston provides an insightful analysis of the emergence and persistence of child poverty in New Zealand. His remarks on why child poverty matters are brief but, as he reports, “[t]here is a large and robust body of research on the harmful consequences of child poverty”. One cost he does not explicitly mention is the increased risk of maltreatment faced by children living in poverty. Given the clear correlation between risk of abuse and poverty, Boston’s recommendations might be expected…Read more
  •  19
    Ethics and the law: an introduction
    Legal Ethics 19 (1): 182-185. 2016.
    x.2016.1190103.