•  177
    One striking oddity about Democritus and Epicurus is that, even though Epicurus' theory of perception is largely the same as that of Democritus, Democritus and his followers draw skeptical conclusions from this theory of perception, whereas Epicurus declares that all perceptions are true or real. I believe that the dispute between Democritus and Epicurus stems from a question over what sort of ontological status should be assigned to sensible qualities. In this paper, I address three questions: …Read more
  •  69
    Epicurus
    In Chiara Rover (ed.), Encyclopedia of Scepticism and Jewish Tradition, Brill. forthcoming.
    Encyclopedia entry on Epicurus' theology. It considers the negative side of Epicurean theology and its basis in their physics, the Epicureans’ positive view of the nature of the gods and how they use it to critique popular religion, and the psychological benefits that they claim result from having correct views about the gods.
  •  257
    The Annicerean Cyrenaics on Friendship and Habitual Good Will
    Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy 62 (3): 305-318. 2017.
    Unlike mainstream Cyrenaics, the Annicereans deny that friendship is chosen only because of its usefulness. Instead, the wise person cares for her friend and endures pains for him because of her goodwill and love. Nonetheless, the Annicereans maintain that your own pleasure is the telos and that a friend’s happiness isn’t intrinsically choiceworthy. Their position appears internally inconsistent or to attribute doublethink to the wise person. But we can avoid these problems. We have good textual…Read more
  •  349
    The Normativity of Nature in Epicurean Ethics and Politics
    In Christof Rapp & Peter Adamson (eds.), State and Nature: Essays in Ancient Political Philosophy, De Gruyter. pp. 181-199. 2021.
    Appeals to nature are ubiquitous in Epicurean ethics and politics. The foundation of Epicurean ethics is its claim that pleasure is the sole intrinsic good and pain the sole intrinsic evil, and this is supposedly shown by the behavior of infants who have not yet been corrupted, "when nature's judgement is pure and whole." Central to their recommendations about how to attain pleasure is their division between types of desires: the natural and necessary ones, the natural but non-necessary ones, an…Read more
  •  51
    Facing Death (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 26 (2): 430-435. 2006.
  •  8
    Epicurus
    Oxford Bibliographies. 2015.
    Select annotated bibliography of works on Epicurus and Epicureanism, organized by subject. First published in 2015 but periodically updated since then.
  •  221
    Positive review of Sellars' short introduction to Epicureanism considered as a way of life.
  •  526
    The Epicureanism of Lucretius
    In David Konstan, Myrto Garani & Gretchen Reydams-Schils (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Roman Philosophy, Oxford University Press, Usa. pp. 143-158. 2022.
    What is distinctive about Lucretius’s version of Epicureanism? The answer might appear to be “nothing,” for two reasons. First, Epicureanism in general is doctrinally conservative, with followers of Epicurus claiming to follow his authority. Second, Lucretius claims to be merely transmitting the arguments of his beloved master Epicurus in a pleasing manner. I argue that these considerations do not prevent De Rerum Natura from presenting a distinct version of Epicureanism. Its arguments in physi…Read more
  •  112
    Ancient Theories of Freedom and Determinism
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 00-00. 2020.
    A fairly long (~15,000 word) overview of ancient theories of freedom and determinism. It covers the supposed threat of causal determinism to "free will," i.e., the sort of control we need to have in order to be rightly held responsible for our actions. But it also discusses fatalistic arguments that proceed from the Principle of Bivalence, what responsibility we have for our own characters, and god and fate. Philosophers discussed include Aristotle, Epicurus, the Stoics, Carneades, Alexander of …Read more
  •  643
    Explores the role of eliminating fear in Epicurean ethics and physics, focusing on techniques to eliminate the fear of death and the fear of the gods.
  •  51
    Epicurus
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2001.
    Overview of Epicurus' philosophy, including his metaphysics, theory of knowledge, and ethics.
  •  458
    Epicurus thought that the conventional values of Greek society—in particular, its celebration of luxury and wealth—often led people astray. It is by rejecting these values, reducing our desires, and leading a moderately ascetic life that we can attain happiness. But Epicurus’ message is also pertinent for those of us in modern Western culture, with an economy based on constant consumption and an advertising industry that molds us to serve that economy by enlarging our desires. This paper begins …Read more
  •  203
    The first part of this paper looks into the question of Lucretius’ philosophical sources and whether he draws almost exclusively from Epicurus himself or also from later Epicurean texts. I argue that such debates are inconclusive and likely will remain so, even if additional Epicurean texts are discovered, and that even if we were able to ascertain Lucretius’ philosophical sources, doing so would add little to our understanding of the De Rerum Natura. The second part of the paper turns to a cons…Read more
  • Epicurus on Reductionism, Determinism and Freedom
    Dissertation, The University of Texas at Austin. 1997.
    Because of the "swerve," it is often thought that Epicurus is the first philosopher to offer a libertarian solution to the so-called "problem of free will." I argue that Epicurus is not a libertarian. The rest of Epicurus' philosophy is incompatible with libertarianism. Epicurus is a materialist and a reductionist. Only atoms and void exist per se, and all events are explicable in terms of the mechanical interaction of atoms. This reductionism holds in his philosophy of mind also: the mind is id…Read more
  •  47
    Lucretius on Atomic Motion (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 23 (2): 461-468. 2003.
  •  180
    Anaxarchus on Indifference, Happiness, and Convention
    In Wolfsdorf David (ed.), Ancient Greek Ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 680-699. 2020.
    Anaxarchus accompanied Pyrrho on Alexander the Great’s expedition to India and was known as “the Happy Man” because of his impassivity and contentment. Our sources on his philosophy are limited and largely consist of anecdotes about his interactions with Pyrrho and Alexander, but they allow us to reconstruct a distinctive ethical position. It overlaps with several disparate ethical traditions but is not merely a hodge-podge; it hangs together as a unified whole. Like Pyrrho, he asserts that thin…Read more
  •  39
    Metaphysics Epsilon 2-3 and Nicomachean Ethics III 5 (1114b3-25) are often cited in favor of indeterminist interpretations of Aristotle. In Metaphysics Epsilon Aristotle denies that the coincidental has an aitia, and some (e.g., Sorabji) take this as a denial that coincidences have causes. In NE III 5 Aristotle says a person's actions and character must have their origin (archê) in the agent for him to be responsible for them. From this, some conclude that Aristotle thinks a person can be the un…Read more
  •  59
    Epicurus on freedom
    Cambridge University Press. 2005.
    In this book, Tim O'Keefe reconstructs the theory of freedom of the ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus (341-271/0 BCE). Epicurus' theory has attracted much interest, but our attempts to understand it have been hampered by reading it anachronistically as the discovery of the modern problem of free will and determinism. O'Keefe argues that the sort of freedom which Epicurus wanted to preserve is significantly different from the 'free will' which philosophers debate today, and that in its emphasis …Read more
  •  29
    Anaxarchus
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2006.
    Overview of the philosophy of this atomist, sophist, and compatriot of Pyrrho.
  •  411
    The Epicureans on happiness, wealth, and the deviant craft of property management
    In Jennifer Baker & Mark White (eds.), Economics and the Virtues, Oxford University Press. pp. 37-52. 2016.
    The Epicureans advocate a moderately ascetic lifestyle on instrumental grounds, as the most effective means to securing tranquility. The virtuous person will reduce his desires to what is natural and necessary in order to avoid the trouble and anxiety caused by excessive desire. So much is clear from Epicurus' general ethics. But the later Epicurean Philodemus fills in far more detail about the attitude a wise Epicurean will take toward wealth in his treatise On Property Management. This paper e…Read more
  •  756
    In De Rerum Natura III 963-971, Lucretius argues that death should not be feared because it is a necessary part of the natural cycle of life and death. This argument has received little philosophical attention, except by Martha Nussbaum, who asserts it is quite strong. However, Nussbaum's view is unsustainable, and I offer my own reading. I agree with Nussbaum that, as she construes it, the cycle of life argument is quite distinct from the better-known Epicurean arguments: not only does it start…Read more
  •  53
    Critical examination of chapter 5 of Julia Annas' book _Platonic Ethics Old and New._ I first argue that she does not establish that Plato's ethics are independent of his metaphysics. I then suggest several ways in the content of his ethics does depend on his metaphysics, with special attention paid to the discussion of the impact of theology on ethics in the _Laws_.
  •  80
    Would a Community of Wise Epicureans Be Just?
    Ancient Philosophy 21 (1): 133-146. 2001.
    I begin by considering an argument for why there would not be justice in a community of wise Epicureans: justice only exists where there is an agreement "neither to harm nor be harmed," and such an agreement would be superfluous in a community of wise Epicureans, since they would have no vain desires which would lead them to wish to harm one another. I argue that, if the 'justice contract' prohibits only direct harm of one person by another, then it would be superfluous among Epicureans. However…Read more
  •  122
    Does Epicurus Need the Swerve as an Archê of Collisions?
    Phronesis 41 (3): 305-317. 1996.
    The 'swerve' is not supposed to provide a temporal 'starting point' (archê) of collisions, since Epicurus thinks that there is no temporal starting-point of collisions. Instead, the swerve is supposed to provide an explanatory archê of collisions. In positing the swerve, Epicurus is responding to Aristotle's criticisms of Democritus' theory of motion.
  •  56
    Ugo Zilioli, The Cyrenaics (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 1 0-0. 2013.
    Argues that many of Zilioli's main contentions are mistaken--in particular, his contention that the Cyrenaics' skepticism is based upon an ambitious metaphysical thesis of indeterminacy.
  •  284
    Focuses on the theories of the Epicureans and Cyrenaics in light of Plato's and Aristotle's criticisms of hedonism. Closes with a brief discussion of how the Pyrrhonian skeptical conception of the telos compares to the Epicureans'.