•  7
    Truth
    In Michael Devitt & Richard Hanley (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language, Wiley-blackwell. 2006.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Plato's Theory Convention T Tarski's Theory of Truth The Liar Paradox Disquotation and Correspondence.
  •  76
    Tarski’s staggering existential assumptions
    Synthese 142 (3): 371-387. 2005.
  •  196
    A puzzle about de rebus beliefs
    Analysis 60 (4). 2000.
    George Boolos (1984, 1985) has extensively investigated plural quantifi- cation, as found in such locutions as the Geach-Kaplan sentence There are critics who admire only one another, and he found that their logic cannot be adequately formalized within the first-order predicate calculus. If we try to formalize the sentence by a paraphrase using individual variables that range over critics, or over sets or collections or fusions of critics, we misrepresent its logical structure. To represent plural…Read more
  •  19
    Logic, Logic, and Logic
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1): 58-62. 2001.
  • The categoricity of logic
    In Colin R. Caret & Ole T. Hjortland (eds.), Foundations of Logical Consequence, Oxford University Press. 2015.
  •  81
    If P, then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1): 239-242. 1992.
  •  178
    The Lessons of the Many
    with Brian P. McLaughlin
    Philosophical Topics 28 (1): 129-151. 2000.
  •  110
    An Epistemic Principle Which Solves Newcomb's Paradox
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 40 (1): 197-217. 1991.
    If it is certain that performing an observation to determine whether P is true will in no way influence whether P is tme, then the proposition that the observation is performed ought to be probabilistically independent of P. Applying the notion of "observation" liberally, so that a wide variety of actions are treated as observations, this proposed new principle of belief revision yields the result that simple utihty maximization gives the correct solution to the Fisher smoking paradox and the tw…Read more
  •  17
    An Epistemic Principle Which Solves Newcomb's Paradox
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 40 (1): 197-217. 1991.
    If it is certain that performing an observation to determine whether P is true will in no way influence whether P is tme, then the proposition that the observation is performed ought to be probabilistically independent of P. Applying the notion of "observation" liberally, so that a wide variety of actions are treated as observations, this proposed new principle of belief revision yields the result that simple utihty maximization gives the correct solution to the Fisher smoking paradox and the tw…Read more
  • Ramsey's Dialetheism
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, Clarendon Press. 2006.
  •  50
    Whittle’s assault on Cantor’s paradise
    Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 9. 2015.
    This chapter presents a response to Chapter 1. The arguments put forward in that chapter attempted to drive us from the paradise created by Cantor’s theory of infinite number. The principal complaint is that Cantor’s proof that the subsets of a set are more numerous than its elements fails to yield an adequate diagnosis of Russell’s paradox. This chapter argues that Cantor’s proof was never meant to be a diagnosis of Russell’s paradox. Further, it argues that Cantor’s theory is fine as it is.
  •  86
    The Revision Theory of Truth (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 727-730. 1996.
  •  46
    Timothy Williamson, Vagueness: London and New York: 1994 (review)
    Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (2): 221-235. 1998.
  •  35
    The Concept of Logical Consequence
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1): 254-255. 1992.
  •  47
    The Concept of Logical Consequence
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3): 379-380. 2001.
  •  65
    A Structuralist Theory of Logic (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 90 (5): 271-274. 1993.
  •  22
  •  105
    XIII*—Two Problems with Tarski's Theory of Consequence
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92 (1): 273-292. 1992.
    Vann McGee; XIII*—Two Problems with Tarski's Theory of Consequence, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 92, Issue 1, 1 June 1992, Pages 273–292, htt.
  • Omnibus Review (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1): 329-332. 1991.
    Reviewed Works:S. N. Artemov, B. M. Schein, Arithmetically Complete Modal Theories.S. N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, On Modal Logics Axiomatizing Provability.S.N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, Nonarithmeticity of Truth Prdicate Logics of Provability.V. A. Vardanyan, E. Mendelson, Arithmetic Complexity of Predicate Logics of Provability and Their.S. N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, Numerically Correct Provability Logics.
  • Truth and Necessity in Partially Interpreted Languages
    Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. 1985.
    Tarski showed how to give satisfactory theories of truth for a wide variety of languages, but he required that the theory of truth for a language be formulated in an essentially richer metalanguage. Since there is no human language essentially richer than a natural language and since we would like to develop consistent theories of truth for natural languages, we would like to learn how to formulate a theory of truth for a language within that very language. ;Toward this end, I consider a class o…Read more
  •  2
    University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, June 3–7, 2000
    with A. Pillay, D. Hallett, G. Hjorth, C. Jockusch, A. Kanamori, and H. J. Keisler
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (3). 2000.
  •  26
    To tell the Truth about Conditionals
    Analysis 60 (1): 107-111. 2000.
  •  341
    How we learn mathematical language
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 35-68. 1997.
    Mathematical realism is the doctrine that mathematical objects really exist, that mathematical statements are either determinately true or determinately false, and that the accepted mathematical axioms are predominantly true. A realist understanding of set theory has it that when the sentences of the language of set theory are understood in their standard meaning, each sentence has a determinate truth value, so that there is a fact of the matter whether the cardinality of the continuum is א2 or …Read more
  •  98
    Truth by default
    Philosophia Mathematica 9 (1): 5-20. 2001.
    There is no preferred reduction of number theory to set theory. Nonetheless, we confidently accept axioms obtained by substituting formulas from the language of set theory into the induction axiom schema. This is only possible, it is argued, because our acceptance of the induction axioms depends solely on the meanings of aritlunetical and logical terms, which is only possible if our 'intended models' of number theory are standard. Similarly, our acceptance of the second-order natural deduction r…Read more
  •  2
    Critical Studies / Book Reviews (review)
    Philosophia Mathematica 12 (3): 278-284. 2004.
  •  15
    [Omnibus Review]
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1): 329-332. 1991.
    Reviewed Works:S. N. Artemov, B. M. Schein, Arithmetically Complete Modal Theories.S. N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, On Modal Logics Axiomatizing Provability.S.N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, Nonarithmeticity of Truth Prdicate Logics of Provability.V. A. Vardanyan, E. Mendelson, Arithmetic Complexity of Predicate Logics of Provability and Their.S. N. Artemov, E. Mendelson, Numerically Correct Provability Logics