•  65
    Time, tense, and reference
    Philosophia 32 (1-4): 423-433. 2005.
  •  233
    Connexive class logic
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (1): 83-90. 1967.
  •  1
    A Model of the Universe
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (186): 113-115. 1994.
  •  50
    Reviews (review)
    with William H. Hanson, Gilbert Harman, N. L. Wilson, M. J. Cresswell, and Margaret D. Wilson
    Synthese 26 (1): 146-178. 1973.
  •  19
    Fate, Logic and Time (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 65 (22): 742-746. 1968.
  •  7
    Critical notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (4): 663-680. 1985.
  •  87
    The ontology of time
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1). 2008.
  •  35
    Starting and Stopping.Instants and Intervals
    with C. L. Hamblin, J. T. Fraser, F. C. Haber, and G. H. Muller
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1): 99. 1975.
  •  30
    Pure three-valued łukasiewiczian implication
    with R. K. Meyer
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3): 399-405. 1966.
  •  121
    A dynamic model of temporal becoming
    Analysis 44 (4): 172-176. 1984.
  •  29
    Incline Without Necessitating
    Dialogue 24 (4): 589-. 1985.
    A stranger runs out of a bank while I am sitting at the wheel of my car waiting for the lights to change; he jumps in beside me, points a gun at me, and says, “Drive me to St. Bruno.” This is Andre Gombay's example, from his excellent paper on duress. The question that interests Gombay and me is: Could I refrain from doing what the gunman asks?
  •  215
    Does the Brain Lead the Mind?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (2): 262-265. 2013.
    Over the last 25 years, experimental findings published by Benjamin Libet have indicated that conscious acts of will are preceded by a characteristic kind of brain event of which the agent is not conscious. It, Libet says, rather than the will, is what causes actions. His discoveries, if correct, would seem to imply that the notion of a free, conscious will is an illusion, and that actions are initiated by neural processes not under conscious control. In what follows it is argued that Libet’s co…Read more
  •  284
    The definition of endurance
    with E. J. Lowe
    Analysis 69 (2): 277-280. 2009.
    David Lewis, following in the tradition of Broad, Quine and Goodman, says that change in an object X consists in X's being temporally extended and having qualitatively different temporal parts. Analogously, change in a spatially extended object such as a road consists in its having different spatial parts . The alternative to this view is that ordinary objects undergo temporal change in virtue of having different intrinsic non-relational properties at different times. They endure, remaining the …Read more
  •  36
    Review: Jean-Louis Gardies, La Logique du Temps (review)
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (3): 430-432. 1977.
  •  44
    Aristotle's modal syllogisms
    North-Holland Pub. Co.. 1963.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work is in the public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity has a copyright on the body of the work. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be preserved, reproduced, and made generally available to the public. To …Read more
  •  446
    Objective time flow
    Philosophy of Science 43 (3): 337-362. 1976.
    A theory of temporal passage is put forward which is "objective" in the sense that time flow characterizes the universe independently of the existence of conscious beings. The theory differs from Grunbaum's "mind-dependence" theory, and is designed to avoid Grunbaum's criticisms of an earlier theory of Reichenbach's. The representation of temporal becoming is accomplished by the introduction of indeterministic universe-models; each model representing the universe at a time. The models depict the…Read more
  •  15
    An Aristotelian Dilemma
    with Jaakko Hintikka and Nicholas Rescher
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2): 418-419. 1972.
  •  156
    God’s lottery
    with D. M. Armstrong
    Analysis 49 (4). 1989.
  •  25
    Contrariety
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 8 (1-2): 121-132. 1967.
  •  18
    The evolution of a single trapped ion exhibiting intermittent fluorescence and dark periods may be described either as a continuous process, using differential rate equations, or discretely, as a Markov process. The latter models the atom as making instantaneous transitions from one energy eigenstate to another, and is open to the objection that superpositions of energy states will form which are not covered by the Markov process. The superposition objection is replied to, and two new mathematic…Read more
  •  11
    The Paradox of Foreknowledge
    Dialogue 6 (2): 229-230. 1967.
    What fourth dimension of a four-dimensional space-time continuum. I propose to develop some of the commonly held implications of this view, and to show that they involve a contradiction. Hence whatever time is, it cannot be the thing corresponding to this particular theory.
  •  73
    Time and the Physical Modalities
    The Monist 53 (3): 426-446. 1969.
    Relative to any point in time, how many possible futures are there? For example, it may rain tomorrow, or again it may not. So it would appear that relative to today, there are at least two possible futures, one involving rain tomorrow and the other not. Of course only one of these two future states of affairs will take place, and in that sense there is only one actual future, though there may be many possible futures. The only hypothesis under which there is, for every instant in time, only one…Read more