•  18
    Gottlob Frege (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 29 287-290. 1982.
  •  55
  •  142
    Belief about Nothing in Particular
    In Mark Eli Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Clarendon Press. pp. 178. 2005.
  •  111
    Rationality and epistemic paradox
    Synthese 94 (3). 1993.
    This paper provides a new solution to the epistemic paradox of belief-instability, a problem of rational choice which has recently received considerable attention (versions of the problem have been discussed by — among others — Tyler Burge, Earl Conee, and Roy Sorensen). The problem involves an ideally rational agent who has good reason to believe the truth of something of the form:[Ap] p if and only if it is not the case that I accept or believe p.
  •  86
    Attempts to analyze negative existential statements face the following familiar problem. If a negative existential statement—say, “Hamlet does not exist” or “the golden mountain does not exist”—is true, its subject term must lack an object of reference. But, absent such an object, it seems that nothing true or false can be said about “it.” In particular, if there is no Hamlet to talk about, we surely cannot truthfully say that “he” does not exist. Hence, the truth of true negative existentials—a…Read more
  •  75
    Kant and Kripke on the Identifiability of Modal and Epistemic Notions
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (1): 49-60. 1981.
    It is sometimes claimed that kripke's work in "naming and necessity" has demonstrated that kant was "right" in his acceptance of the synthetic "a priori", Even though perhaps "wrong" in his choice of examples. This article disputes such a claim by showing that, In accepting the identification of the empirically necessary and the "a priori", Kant's position is incompatible with an acceptance of the kripkean synthetic "a priori" (as well as the kripkean necessary "a posteriori")
  •  89
    Fear and Integrity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (1): 31-49. 2008.
    I'll begin this paper with an autobiographical example — an instance of a common enough kind of case involving agents who are faced with making a choice they strongly care about, but who have tendencies that incline them towards choosing an option they prefer not to choose. Later in the paper, I apply some of the general lessons learned from this case to a philosophically more familiar example of a hard-to-make choice, and to the well-known problem the example generates for the idea of rational …Read more
  •  198
    Theory-dependence, warranted reference, and the epistemic dimensions of realism
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (2): 173-191. 2011.
    The question of the role of theory in the determination of reference of theoretical terms continues to be a controversial one. In the present paper I assess a number of responses to this question (including variations on David Lewis’s appeal to Ramsification), before describing an alternative, epistemically oriented account of the reference-determination of such terms. The paper concludes by discussing some implications of the account for our understanding of both realism and such competitors of…Read more
  •  408
    Causal descriptivism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (1). 1987.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  • The Fiction of Creationism
    In Franck Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction, Ontos Verlag. pp. 38--203. 2010.
  •  52
    Plantinga on God, freedom, and evil
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (2). 1981.
  •  135
    Millian descriptivism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4). 2004.
    Mill is a detractor of the view that proper names have meanings, defending in its place the view that names are nothing more than (meaningless) marks. Because of this, Mill is often regarded as someone who anticipated the theory of direct reference for names: the view that the only contribution a name makes to propositions expressed through its use is the name's referent. In this paper I argue that the association is unfair. With some gentle interpretation, Mill can be portrayed as someone who i…Read more
  • Intending and Imagining
    In Henrik Lagerlund, Sten Lindström & Rysiek Sliwinski (eds.), Modality Matters: Twenty-Five Essays in Honour of Krister Segerberg, Uppsala Philosophical Studies 53. pp. 53--247. 2006.
  •  36
    The Philosophy of Information – By Luciano Floridi
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (1): 86-88. 2012.
  •  64
    Parts and Pretense
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3): 543-560. 2001.
    This paper begins with a puzzle about certain temporal expressions: phrases like ‘Jones as he was ten years ago’ and ‘the Jones of ten years ago’. There are reasons to take these as substantival, to be interpreted as terms for temporal parts. But it seems that the same reifying strategy would also force us to countenance a host of less attractive posits, among them fictional counterparts of real things (to correspond to such phrases as ‘Garrison as he was in the movie JFK') and much more. I argu…Read more
  •  112
    Much ado about nothing: Priest and the reinvention of noneism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1). 2008.
  •  243
    Fictionalism in Metaphysics
    Philosophy Compass 6 (11): 786-803. 2011.
    This is a survey of contemporary work on ‘fictionalism in metaphysics’, a term that is taken to signify both the place of fictionalism as a distinctive anti‐realist metaphysics in which usefulness rather than truth is the norm of acceptance, and the fact that philosophers have given fictionalist treatments of a range of specifically metaphysical notions
  •  284
    Was meinong only pretending?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (3): 499-527. 1992.
    In this paper I argue against the usual interpretation of\nMeinong's argument for nonexistent objects, an\ninterpretation according to which Meinong imported\nnonexistent objects like "the golden mountain" to account\ndirectly for the truth of statements like the golden\nmountain is golden'. I claim instead (using evidence from\nMeinong's "On Assumptions") that his argument really\ninvolves an ineliminable appeal to the notion of pretense.\nThis appeal nearly convinced Meinong at one stage that …Read more
  •  59
    Characterizing Non-existents
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 51 (1): 163-193. 1996.
    Consider predicates like 'is a fictional character' and 'is a mythical object'. Since their ascription entails a corresponding Negative Existential claim, call these 'NE-characterizing predicates'. Objectualists such as Parsons, Sylvan, van Inwagen, and Zalta think that NE-characterizing properties are genuine properties of genuinely non-existent objects. But how, then, to make room for statements like 'Vulcan is a failed posit' and 'that little green man is a trick of the light'? The predicates…Read more
  •  30
  •  2
    A Realistic Theory of Categories (review)
    Dialogue 38 (2): 417-419. 1999.
    Roderick Chisholm’s Essay looks beguilingly simple. It is a short work, written in a simple, unaffected style. There is, of course, the usual crop of technical definitions, but these should not daunt the reader. Chisholm makes it easy enough, for the most part, to see what motivates his formulations, and he makes it easy for his readers to see how his concerns and solutions compare with those of some other important philosophers.
  •  92
    Quantified negative existentials
    Dialectica 57 (2). 2003.
    This paper suggests that quantified negative existentials about fiction—statements of the form “There are some / many / etc. Fs in work W who don't exist”—offer a serious challenge to the theorist of fiction: more serious, in a number of ways, that singular negative existentials. I argue that the temptation to think that only a realist semantics of such statements is plausible should be resisted. There are numerous quantified negative existentials found in other areas that seem equally “true” bu…Read more
  •  34
    Mind, Ethics, and Conditionals: Themes from the Philosophy of Frank Jackson
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2). 2011.
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 89, Issue 2, Page 367-370, June 2011
  •  86
    Imaginative motivation
    Utilitas 21 (2): 181-196. 2009.
    This article argues for a certain picture of the rational formation of conditional intentions, in particular deterrent intentions, that stands in sharp contrast to accounts on which rational agents are often not able to form such intentions because of what these enjoin should their conditions be realized. By considering the case of worthwhile but hard-to-form deterrent intentions (the threat to leave a cheating partner, say), the article argues that rational agents may be able to form such inten…Read more
  •  296
    Descriptivism, Pretense, and the Frege-Russell Problems
    Philosophical Review 113 (1): 1-30. 2004.
    Contrary to frequent declarations that descriptivism as a theory of how names refer is dead and gone, such a descriptivism is, to all appearances, alive and well. Or rather, a descendent of that doctrine is alive and well. This new version—neo-descriptivism, for short—is supposedly immune from the usual arguments against descriptivism, in large part because it avoids classical descriptivism’s emphasis on salient, first-come-to-mind properties and holds instead that a name’s reference-fixing cont…Read more