•  52
    Plantinga on God, freedom, and evil
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (2). 1981.
  •  135
    Millian descriptivism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4). 2004.
    Mill is a detractor of the view that proper names have meanings, defending in its place the view that names are nothing more than (meaningless) marks. Because of this, Mill is often regarded as someone who anticipated the theory of direct reference for names: the view that the only contribution a name makes to propositions expressed through its use is the name's referent. In this paper I argue that the association is unfair. With some gentle interpretation, Mill can be portrayed as someone who i…Read more
  • Intending and Imagining
    In Henrik Lagerlund, Sten Lindström & Rysiek Sliwinski (eds.), Modality Matters: Twenty-Five Essays in Honour of Krister Segerberg, Uppsala Philosophical Studies 53. pp. 53--247. 2006.
  •  36
    The Philosophy of Information – By Luciano Floridi
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (1): 86-88. 2012.
  •  64
    Parts and Pretense
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3): 543-560. 2001.
    This paper begins with a puzzle about certain temporal expressions: phrases like ‘Jones as he was ten years ago’ and ‘the Jones of ten years ago’. There are reasons to take these as substantival, to be interpreted as terms for temporal parts. But it seems that the same reifying strategy would also force us to countenance a host of less attractive posits, among them fictional counterparts of real things (to correspond to such phrases as ‘Garrison as he was in the movie JFK') and much more. I argu…Read more
  •  112
    Much ado about nothing: Priest and the reinvention of noneism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1). 2008.
  •  284
    Was meinong only pretending?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (3): 499-527. 1992.
    In this paper I argue against the usual interpretation of\nMeinong's argument for nonexistent objects, an\ninterpretation according to which Meinong imported\nnonexistent objects like "the golden mountain" to account\ndirectly for the truth of statements like the golden\nmountain is golden'. I claim instead (using evidence from\nMeinong's "On Assumptions") that his argument really\ninvolves an ineliminable appeal to the notion of pretense.\nThis appeal nearly convinced Meinong at one stage that …Read more
  •  243
    Fictionalism in Metaphysics
    Philosophy Compass 6 (11): 786-803. 2011.
    This is a survey of contemporary work on ‘fictionalism in metaphysics’, a term that is taken to signify both the place of fictionalism as a distinctive anti‐realist metaphysics in which usefulness rather than truth is the norm of acceptance, and the fact that philosophers have given fictionalist treatments of a range of specifically metaphysical notions
  •  30
  •  59
    Characterizing Non-existents
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 51 (1): 163-193. 1996.
    Consider predicates like 'is a fictional character' and 'is a mythical object'. Since their ascription entails a corresponding Negative Existential claim, call these 'NE-characterizing predicates'. Objectualists such as Parsons, Sylvan, van Inwagen, and Zalta think that NE-characterizing properties are genuine properties of genuinely non-existent objects. But how, then, to make room for statements like 'Vulcan is a failed posit' and 'that little green man is a trick of the light'? The predicates…Read more
  •  92
    Quantified negative existentials
    Dialectica 57 (2). 2003.
    This paper suggests that quantified negative existentials about fiction—statements of the form “There are some / many / etc. Fs in work W who don't exist”—offer a serious challenge to the theorist of fiction: more serious, in a number of ways, that singular negative existentials. I argue that the temptation to think that only a realist semantics of such statements is plausible should be resisted. There are numerous quantified negative existentials found in other areas that seem equally “true” bu…Read more
  •  2
    A Realistic Theory of Categories (review)
    Dialogue 38 (2): 417-419. 1999.
    Roderick Chisholm’s Essay looks beguilingly simple. It is a short work, written in a simple, unaffected style. There is, of course, the usual crop of technical definitions, but these should not daunt the reader. Chisholm makes it easy enough, for the most part, to see what motivates his formulations, and he makes it easy for his readers to see how his concerns and solutions compare with those of some other important philosophers.
  •  34
    Mind, Ethics, and Conditionals: Themes from the Philosophy of Frank Jackson
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2). 2011.
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 89, Issue 2, Page 367-370, June 2011