•  164
    In Republic V, Plato distinguishes two different cognitive powers, knowledge and belief, which operate differently on different types of object. I argue that in Republic VI Plato modifies this account, and claims that there is a single cognitive power, which under different circumstances behaves either as knowledge or as belief. I show that the circumstances which turn true belief into knowledge are the provision of an individuation account of the object of belief, which reveals the ontological …Read more
  •  35
    The uniqueness of particulars
    Philosophia 14 (3-4): 273-297. 1984.
  •  31
    Aristotle on Substance — The Paradox of Unity
    Philosophical Books 32 (1): 26-28. 1991.
  •  83
    Substratum, Subject, and Substance
    Ancient Philosophy 5 (2): 215-240. 1985.
  •  3
    Sharing a property
    In Lindsay Judson & Vassilis Karasmanis (eds.), Remembering Socrates: philosophical essays, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  2
  •  45
    XIII*—Fairness in Socratic Justice—Republic I†
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1): 247-262. 1993.
    Theodore Scaltsas; XIII*—Fairness in Socratic Justice—Republic I†, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 93, Issue 1, 1 June 1993, Pages 247–262, http.
  •  97
    In Republic V, Plato makes the astonishing claim that knowledge is a different and independent power from belief, in the way, for example, that sight differs from hearing. I will argue that this is a fundamentally different conception of knowledge than the, also Platonic, conception of knowledge as 'true belief with an account'. I examine the reasons why Plato holds this position, and the ontology and epistemology which sustain its claims.
  • Sharing a property
    In Lindsay Judson & Vassilis Karasmanis (eds.), Remembering Socrates: philosophical essays, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  20
    Substance, Form and Psyche: An Aristotelian Metaphysics
    Philosophical Books 30 (2): 82-85. 1989.
  •  19
    Parallel Governing
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2): 153-158. 1990.
    ABSTRACT Parallel processing systems can carry out computational tasks which would be impossible to be carried out by sequential systems. Cognitive psychologists are discovering that brains do not operate on a sequential ordering of tasks, but along parallel processing models. Sequential ordering is abandoned in the new generation computers, which are being designed on evolving parallel processing models. My proposal consists in applying the parallel processing principles to the state, creating …Read more
  •  61
    Knowledge as ‘True Belief Plus Individuation’ in Plato
    Philosophical Inquiry 38 (3-4): 20-41. 2014.
    In Republic V, Plato distinguishes two different cognitive powers, knowledge and belief, which operate differently on different types of object. I argue that in Republic VI Plato modifies this account, and claims that there is a single cognitive power, which under different circumstances behaves either as knowledge or as belief. I show that the circumstances which turn true belief into knowledge are the provision of an individuation account of the object of belief, which reveals the ontological …Read more
  •  90
    Weakness of Will in Aristotle’s Ethics
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (3): 375-382. 1986.
    I argue that in "en", Aristotle allows not only for weak akrasia but also for "strong akrasia". In weak akrasia, The agent makes only a "nominal" choice according to the right principle, While in strong akrasia he/she makes a "real" choice, But still acts against it. I show that, Although aristotle does not give a detailed account of strong akrasia, Such an account can be reconstructed on the basis of the analyses and examples of choice and akratic behaviour provided by him in "en" and "de motu"
  •  20
    Substratum, Subject, and Substance
    Ancient Philosophy 5 (2): 215-240. 1985.
  •  29
    Sharing a Property
    Philosophical Inquiry 41 (2-3): 3-16. 2017.
    The Socratic discussion in the Hippias Major, 300-303, is not a passing comment on plural reference; it is a theory of plural subjecthood. It has escaped attention because it is a small part of a larger complex argument on the topic of which pleasures are fine. Socrates’s theory is further concealed by the fact that it is presented as an antithesis between Hippias and himself, whereas in fact, Hippias’s position becomes part of Socrates’s theory. I begin by examining Hippias’s position, and subs…Read more
  •  62
  •  44
    Identity, Individuation, and Uniqueness in Stoics Metaphysics
    Philosophical Inquiry 34 (1-2): 1-14. 2011.
  •  62
    The philosophy of Epictetus (edited book)
    with Andrew S. Mason
    Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Written by some of the leading experts in the field, the essays in this volume will be a fascinating resource for students and scholars of ancient philosophy, ...
  • Brill Online Books and Journals
    with M. F. Burnyeat, Daniel W. Graham, G. E. R. Lloyd, Jonathan Lear, and Charles H. Kahn
    Phronesis 37 (2). 1992.
  •  103
    Substantial Holism
    Philosophical Inquiry 39 (1): 146-163. 2015.
  •  178
    Relations as Plural-Predications in Plato
    Studia Neoaristotelica 10 (1): 28-49. 2013.
    Plato was the first philosopher to discover the metaphysical phenomenon of plural-subjects and plural-predication; e.g. you and I are two, but neither you, nor I are two. I argue that Plato devised an ontology for plural-predication through his Theory of Forms, namely, plural-partaking in a Form. Furthermore, I argue that Plato used plural-partaking to offer an ontology of related individuals without reifying relations. My contention is that Plato’s theory of plural-relatives has evaded detectio…Read more
  • M. Burnyeat , "The Skeptical Tradition" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (50): 130. 1988.