•  178
    Relations as Plural-Predications in Plato
    Studia Neoaristotelica 10 (1): 28-49. 2013.
    Plato was the first philosopher to discover the metaphysical phenomenon of plural-subjects and plural-predication; e.g. you and I are two, but neither you, nor I are two. I argue that Plato devised an ontology for plural-predication through his Theory of Forms, namely, plural-partaking in a Form. Furthermore, I argue that Plato used plural-partaking to offer an ontology of related individuals without reifying relations. My contention is that Plato’s theory of plural-relatives has evaded detectio…Read more
  • M. Burnyeat , "The Skeptical Tradition" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 38 (50): 130. 1988.
  •  24
    Commentary on Gotthelf
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 4 (1): 140-147. 1988.
  •  35
    Weakness of Will in Aristotle's Ethics
    Philosophical Inquiry 40 (1-2): 30-37. 2016.
  •  83
    The Theme A substance is a composite particular. If it is composed of further particulars, will the substance itself be one or many? ...
  •  28
    Mixing the Elements
    In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 242-259. 2009.
    Forthcoming in the Blackwell Companion to Aristotle, 2008.
  •  14
    In search of socrates
    Philosophical Books 34 (3): 129-137. 1993.
  •  29
    The Golden Age of Virtue: Aristotle's Ethics
    Philosophical Quarterly 45 (179): 258. 1995.
  •  202
  •  82
    Reciprocal Justice in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 77 (3): 248-262. 1995.
  •  54
    In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle begins his investigation by exploring the nature of the end of all action. In the very first sentence of the work he says: "Every art and every enquiry and similarly every action and pursuit is thought to aim at some good and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim". It is easy, says Aristotle, to find verbal agreement between people regarding that good because they all consider it to be happiness. Aristotle says: …Read more
  •  16
    Weakness of Will in Aristotle's Ethics
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (3): 375-382. 1986.
  •  101
    In this paper i offer a detailed analysis of the dilemma of participation (parmenides, 130e-131e), in which plato considers the consequences of participation in the whole, and in a part of, a form. This analysis explains, in contrast to existing interpretations of the argument, plato's claim that participation in parts of a form is incompatible with the uniqueness of the form, and his modal claim that becoming equal by possessing part of the equal is absurd. In the second part of the paper, i gi…Read more
  • Substance and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (189): 536-539. 1997.
  •  30
  •  159
    In Republic V, Plato distinguishes two different cognitive powers, knowledge and belief, which operate differently on different types of object. I argue that in Republic VI Plato modifies this account, and claims that there is a single cognitive power, which under different circumstances behaves either as knowledge or as belief. I show that the circumstances which turn true belief into knowledge are the provision of an individuation account of the object of belief, which reveals the ontological …Read more
  •  31
    Aristotle on Substance — The Paradox of Unity
    Philosophical Books 32 (1): 26-28. 1991.
  •  35
    The uniqueness of particulars
    Philosophia 14 (3-4): 273-297. 1984.
  •  83
    Substratum, Subject, and Substance
    Ancient Philosophy 5 (2): 215-240. 1985.
  •  3
    Sharing a property
    In Lindsay Judson & Vassilis Karasmanis (eds.), Remembering Socrates: Philosophical Essays, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  2