•  184
    Deriving General Relativity from String Theory
    Philosophy of Science 82 (5): 1163-1174. 2015.
    Weyl symmetry of the classical bosonic string Lagrangian is broken by quantization, with profound consequences described here. Reimposing symmetry requires that the background space-time satisfy the equations of general relativity: general relativity, hence classical space-time as we know it, arises from string theory. We investigate the logical role of Weyl symmetry in this explanation of general relativity: it is not an independent physical postulate but required in quantum string theory, so f…Read more
  • Critical notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4): 1093. 1999.
  •  17
    Was the first book to examine the exciting area of overlap between philosophy and quantum mechanics with chapters by leading experts from around the world.
  •  1
    Physics Meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, Contemporary Theories in Quantum Gravity
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (3): 531-537. 2001.
  •  10
    Understanding Scientific Theories: An Assessment of Developments, 1969–1998 (review)
    with Steven French and Frederick Suppe
    Philosophy of Science 67 (3). 2000.
    The positivistic Received View construed scientific theories syntactically as axiomatic calculi where theoretical terms were given a partial semantic interpretation via correspondence rules connecting them to observation statements. This paper assesses what, with hindsight, seem the most important defects in the Received View; surveys the main proposed successor analyses to the Received View—various Semantic Conception versions and the Structuralist Analysis; evaluates how well they avoid those …Read more
  •  20
    The two books discussed here make important contributions to our understanding of the role of spacetime concepts in physical theories and how that understanding has changed during the evolution of physics. Both emphasize what can be called a ‘dynamical’ account, according to which geometric structures should be understood in terms of their roles in the laws governing matter and force. I explore how the books contribute to such a project; while generally sympathetic, I offer criticisms of some hi…Read more
  • Introduction
    with Craig Callender
    In Craig Callender & Nick Huggett (eds.), Physics Meets Philosophy at the Panck Scale, Cambridge University Press. 2001.
  •  18
    Philosophy of Physics (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 27 (4): 139-140. 1995.
  •  4
    Learning through original texts can be a powerful heuristic tool. This book collects a dozen classic readings that are generally accepted as the most significant contributions to the philosophy of space. The readings have been selected both on the basis of their relevance to recent debates on the nature of space and on the extent to which they carry premonitions of contemporary physics. In his detailed commentaries, Nick Huggett weaves together the readings and links them to our modern understan…Read more
  •  375
    Why is our knowledge of the past so much more ‘expansive’ (to pick a suitably vague term) than our knowledge of the future, and what is the best way to capture the difference(s) (i.e., in what sense is knowledge of the past more ‘expansive’)? One could reasonably approach these questions by giving necessary conditions for different kinds of knowledge, and showing how some were satisfied by certain propositions about the past, and not by corresponding propositions about the future. I take it that…Read more
  •  72
    Review of David Z. Albert, Time and Chance (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (2). 2002.
  •  81
    Mirror symmetry: What is it for relational space to be orientable?
    In Katherine Brading & Elena Castellani (eds.), Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections, Cambridge University Press. pp. 281. 2002.
    As Pooley (2001) explains, the challenge of giving a relational account of orientability (and topology more generally) is not an easy one. This paper criticizes Pooley's and other proposals, raises a range of problems for the project, and then proposes a novel way for the relationist to understand not only topology, but also the geometry of space. This proposal is the `regularity account' since it claims that geometry and topology supervene on the regular ways in which relations evolve
  •  160
    Local philosophies of science
    Philosophy of Science 67 (3): 137. 2000.
    Since the collapse of the 'received view' consensus in the late 1960s, the question of scientific realism has been a major preoccupation of philosophers of science. This paper sketches the history of this debate, which grew from developments in the philosophy of language, but eventually took on an autonomous existence. More recently, the debate has tended towards more 'local' considerations of particular scientific episodes as a way of getting purchase on the issues. The paper reviews two such a…Read more
  •  16
    Gauge fields, gravity and Bohm's theory
    with Robert Weingard
    In Tian Yu Cao (ed.), Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Field Theory, Cambridge University Press. pp. 287-297. 1999.
  •  1
    Philosophy of Physics (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 27 (4): 139-140. 1995.
  •  378
    Why the parts of absolute space are immobile
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (3): 391-407. 2008.
    Newton's arguments for the immobility of the parts of absolute space have been claimed to licence several proposals concerning his metaphysics. This paper clarifies Newton, first distinguishing two distinct arguments. Then, it demonstrates, contrary to Nerlich ([2005]), that Newton does not appeal to the identity of indiscernibles, but rather to a view about de re representation. Additionally, DiSalle ([1994]) claims that one argument shows Newton to be an anti-substantivalist. I agree that its …Read more
  •  25
    The Philosophy of Science (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 21 (4): 416-419. 1998.
  •  59
    A number of commentators (especially French and Redhead, 1988, and Butterfield, 1993) have investigated the status of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles (PII) for bosons and fermions. In this paper I extend that investigation to the full range of quantum particles of any allowed kind of statistics -- `quarticles', that is. I show that for any kind (except bosons and fermions) there are states in which PII is violated by every pair of particles, some pairs and not others, and by no p…Read more
  •  219
    Since antiquity, natural philosophers have struggled to comprehend the nature of three tightly interconnected concepts: space, time, and motion. A proper understanding of motion, in particular, has been seen to be crucial for deciding questions about the natures of space and time, and their interconnections. Since the time of Newton and Leibniz, philosophers’ struggles to comprehend these concepts have often appeared to take the form of a dispute between absolute conceptions of space, time and m…Read more
  •  86
    Where should we begin our story? Many books start with Newton, but Newton was responding to both Galileo1 and especially (for our purposes) Descartes. But Galileo and Descartes themselves were writing in the context of late Aristotelianism, and so were trained in and critical of that rich school of thought, so if we want to fully understand their work we would need to understand scholastic views on space and motion (see Grant, 1974, Murdoch and Sylla, 1978 and Ariew and Gabbey, 1998). But late s…Read more
  •  33
    What did Newton mean by ‘Absolute Motion’?
    In Andrew Janiak & Eric Schliesser (eds.), Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 196-218. 2012.
  •  41
    Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4): 1093-1096. 1999.
  •  91
    Interpretations of quantum field theory
    with Robert Weingard
    Philosophy of Science 61 (3): 370-388. 1994.
    In this paper we critically review the various attempts that have been made to understand quantum field theory. We focus on Teller's (1990) harmonic oscillator interpretation, and Bohm et al.'s (1987) causal interpretation. The former unabashedly aims to be a purely heuristic account, but we show that it is only interestingly applicable to the free bosonic field. Along the way we suggest alternative models. Bohm's interpretation provides an ontology for the theory--a classical field, with a quan…Read more
  •  210
    Weak Discernibility for Quanta, the Right Way
    with Josh Norton
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (1): 39-58. 2014.
    Muller and Saunders ([2008]) purport to demonstrate that, surprisingly, bosons and fermions are discernible; this article disputes their arguments, then derives a similar conclusion in a more satisfactory fashion. After briefly explicating their proof and indicating how it escapes earlier indiscernibility results, we note that the observables which Muller and Saunders argue discern particles are (i) non-symmetric in the case of bosons and (ii) trivial multiples of the identity in the case of fer…Read more
  •  47
    This paper has two goals. (i) I explore the limits of the mathematical theory of spacetime (more generally, differential geometry) as an analytical tool for interpreting early modern thought. While it dramatically clarifies some issues, it can also lead to misunderstandings of some figures, and is a very poor tool indeed for others - Leibniz in particular. (ii) I will show how to blunt a very influential argument against a relational conception of spacetime - the view that the properties and rel…Read more
  •  74
    Indistinguishability
    with Tom Imbo
    In Daniel Greenberger, Klaus Hentschel & Friedel Weinert (eds.), Compendium of Quantum Physics, Springer. pp. 311-317. 2009.
    an article written with Tom Imbo for the forthcoming Compendium of Quantum Mechanics.