•  47
    What Are Quanta, and Why Does It Matter?
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994. 1994.
    I criticize a certain view of the 'quanta' of quantum mechanics that sees them as fundamentally non-atomistic and fundamentally significant for our understanding of quantum fields. In particular, I have in mind work by Redhead and Teller (1991, 1992 and Teller 1990). I prove that classical particles do not have the rather strong flavour of identity often associated with them; permuting positions and momenta does not produce distinct states. I show that even the label free excitation formalism is…Read more
  •  96
    Skeptical notes on a physics of passage
    Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1326 (1): 9-17. 2014.
    This paper investigates the mathematical representation of time in physics. In existing theories time is represented by the real numbers, hence their formal proper- ties represent properties of time: these are surveyed. The central question of the paper is whether the existing representation of time is adequate, or whether it can or should be supplemented: especially, do we need a physics incorporating some kind of ‘dynamical passage’ of time? The paper argues that the existing mathematical fram…Read more
  •  16
    Gauge fields, gravity and Bohm's theory
    with Robert Weingard
    In Tian Yu Cao (ed.), Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Field Theory, Cambridge University Press. pp. 287-297. 1999.
  •  1
    Philosophy of Physics (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 27 (4): 139-140. 1995.
  •  374
    Why the parts of absolute space are immobile
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (3): 391-407. 2008.
    Newton's arguments for the immobility of the parts of absolute space have been claimed to licence several proposals concerning his metaphysics. This paper clarifies Newton, first distinguishing two distinct arguments. Then, it demonstrates, contrary to Nerlich ([2005]), that Newton does not appeal to the identity of indiscernibles, but rather to a view about de re representation. Additionally, DiSalle ([1994]) claims that one argument shows Newton to be an anti-substantivalist. I agree that its …Read more
  •  25
    The Philosophy of Science (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 21 (4): 416-419. 1998.
  •  59
    A number of commentators (especially French and Redhead, 1988, and Butterfield, 1993) have investigated the status of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles (PII) for bosons and fermions. In this paper I extend that investigation to the full range of quantum particles of any allowed kind of statistics -- `quarticles', that is. I show that for any kind (except bosons and fermions) there are states in which PII is violated by every pair of particles, some pairs and not others, and by no p…Read more
  •  219
    Since antiquity, natural philosophers have struggled to comprehend the nature of three tightly interconnected concepts: space, time, and motion. A proper understanding of motion, in particular, has been seen to be crucial for deciding questions about the natures of space and time, and their interconnections. Since the time of Newton and Leibniz, philosophers’ struggles to comprehend these concepts have often appeared to take the form of a dispute between absolute conceptions of space, time and m…Read more
  •  86
    Where should we begin our story? Many books start with Newton, but Newton was responding to both Galileo1 and especially (for our purposes) Descartes. But Galileo and Descartes themselves were writing in the context of late Aristotelianism, and so were trained in and critical of that rich school of thought, so if we want to fully understand their work we would need to understand scholastic views on space and motion (see Grant, 1974, Murdoch and Sylla, 1978 and Ariew and Gabbey, 1998). But late s…Read more
  •  33
    What did Newton mean by ‘Absolute Motion’?
    In Andrew Janiak & Eric Schliesser (eds.), Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 196-218. 2012.
  •  41
    Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4): 1093-1096. 1999.
  •  91
    Interpretations of quantum field theory
    with Robert Weingard
    Philosophy of Science 61 (3): 370-388. 1994.
    In this paper we critically review the various attempts that have been made to understand quantum field theory. We focus on Teller's (1990) harmonic oscillator interpretation, and Bohm et al.'s (1987) causal interpretation. The former unabashedly aims to be a purely heuristic account, but we show that it is only interestingly applicable to the free bosonic field. Along the way we suggest alternative models. Bohm's interpretation provides an ontology for the theory--a classical field, with a quan…Read more
  •  47
    This paper has two goals. (i) I explore the limits of the mathematical theory of spacetime (more generally, differential geometry) as an analytical tool for interpreting early modern thought. While it dramatically clarifies some issues, it can also lead to misunderstandings of some figures, and is a very poor tool indeed for others - Leibniz in particular. (ii) I will show how to blunt a very influential argument against a relational conception of spacetime - the view that the properties and rel…Read more
  •  207
    Weak Discernibility for Quanta, the Right Way
    with Josh Norton
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (1): 39-58. 2014.
    Muller and Saunders ([2008]) purport to demonstrate that, surprisingly, bosons and fermions are discernible; this article disputes their arguments, then derives a similar conclusion in a more satisfactory fashion. After briefly explicating their proof and indicating how it escapes earlier indiscernibility results, we note that the observables which Muller and Saunders argue discern particles are (i) non-symmetric in the case of bosons and (ii) trivial multiples of the identity in the case of fer…Read more
  •  74
    Indistinguishability
    with Tom Imbo
    In Daniel Greenberger, Klaus Hentschel & Friedel Weinert (eds.), Compendium of Quantum Physics, Springer. pp. 311-317. 2009.
    an article written with Tom Imbo for the forthcoming Compendium of Quantum Mechanics.
  •  160
    The regularity account of relational spacetime
    Mind 115 (457): 41--73. 2006.
    A version of relationism that takes spatiotemporal structures—spatial geometry and a standard of inertia—to supervene on the history of relations between bodies is described and defended. The account is used to explain how the relationist should construe models of Newtonian mechanics in which absolute acceleration manifestly does not supervene on the relations; Ptolemaic and Copernican models for example. The account introduces a new way in which a Lewis-style ‘best system’ might capture regular…Read more
  •  31
    Renormalization and the disunity of science
    In Meinard Kuhlmann, Holger Lyre & Andrew Wayne (eds.), Ontological Aspects of Quantum Field Theory, World Scientific. pp. 255-277. 2002.
  •  275
    Emergent spacetime and empirical (in) coherence
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (3): 276-285. 2013.
    Numerous approaches to a quantum theory of gravity posit fundamental ontologies that exclude spacetime, either partially or wholly. This situation raises deep questions about how such theories could relate to the empirical realm, since arguably only entities localized in spacetime can ever be observed. Are such entities even possible in a theory without fundamental spacetime? How might they be derived, formally speaking? Moreover, since by assumption the fundamental entities cannot be smaller th…Read more
  •  254
    Atomic metaphysics
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (1): 5-24. 1999.
  •  97
    On the significance of permutation symmetry
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (3): 325-347. 1999.
    There has been considerable recent philosophical debate over the implications of many particle quantum mechanics for the metaphysics of individuality (cf. Huggett [1997]). In this paper I look at things from a rather different perspective: by investigating the significance of permutation symmetry. I consider how various philosophical positions link up to the physical postulate of the indistinguishability of permuted states-permutation invariance-and how this postulate is used to explain quantum …Read more
  •  160
    Why manifold substantivalism is probably not a consequence of classical mechanics
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (1). 1999.
    This paper develops and defends three related forms of relationism about spacetime against attacks by contemporary substantivalists. It clarifies Newton's globes argument to show that it does not bear on relations that fail to determine geodesic motions, since the inertial effects on which Newton relies are not simply correlated with affine structure, but must be understood in dynamical terms. It develops remarks by Sklar and van Fraassen into relational versions of Newtonian mechanics, and argu…Read more
  •  103
    Quantum gravity--the marriage of quantum physics with general relativity--is bound to contain deep and important lessons for the nature of physical time. Some of these lessons shall be canvassed here, particularly as they arise from quantum general relativity and string theory and related approaches. Of particular interest is the question of which of the intuitive aspects of time will turn out to be fundamental, and which 'emergent' in some sense