•  120
    Moral relativism and deontic logic
    Synthese 85 (1). 1990.
    If a native of India asserts "Killing cattle is wrong" and a Nebraskan asserts "Killing cattle is not wrong", and both judgments agree with their respective moralities and both moralities are internally consistent, then the moral relativist says both judgments are fully correct. At this point relativism bifurcates. One branch which we call content relativism denies that the two people are contradicting each other. The idea is that the content of a moral judgment is a function of the overall mora…Read more
  •  24
    Steiner versus Wittgenstein: Remarks on Differing Views of Mathematical Truth
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 20 (3): 347-352. 2010.
    Mark Steiner criticizes some remarks Wittgenstein makes about Gödel. Steiner takes Wittgenstein to be disputing a mathematical result. The paper argues that Wittgenstein does no such thing. The contrast between the realist and the demonstrativist concerning mathematical truth is examined. Wittgenstein is held to side with neither camp. Rather, his point is that a realist argument is inconclusive.
  •  52
    Theories of truth and semantical primitives
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1). 1977.
    Robert cummins has recently attacked this line of argument: if p is a semantically primitive predicate of a first order language l, then p requires its own clause in the definition of satisfaction integral to a definition of truth of l. thus if l has infinitely many such p, the satisfaction clause cannot be completed and truth for l will remain undefined. against this cummins argues that a single clause in a general base theory for l can specify satisfaction conditions for even infinitely many s…Read more
  •  47
    A Conversation about Numbers and Knowledge
    American Philosophical Quarterly 39 (3): 275-287. 2002.
    This is a dialogue in the philosophy of mathematics. The dialogue descends from the confident assertion that there are infinitely many numbers to an unresolved bewilderment about how we can know there are any numbers at all. At every turn the dialogue brings us only to realize more fully how little is clear to us in our thinking about mathematics.
  •  29
    Two philosophical theories, mathematical Platonism and nominalism, are the background of six dialogues in this book. There are five characters in these dialogues: three are nominalists; the fourth is a Platonist; the main character is somewhat skeptical on most issues in the philosophy of mathematics, and is particularly skeptical regarding the two background theories.
  •  107
    Expressions and Tokens
    Analysis 41 (4): 181-187. 1981.
    The purpose of this paper is to uncover and correct several confusions about expressions, tokens and the relations between them that crop up in even highly sophisticated writing about language and logic.
  •  70
    Two concepts of truth
    Philosophical Studies 70 (1). 1993.
    In this paper the authors recapitulate, justify, and defend against criticism the extension of the redundancy theory of truth to cover a wide range of uses of ‘true’ and ‘false’. In this they are guided by the work of A. N. Prior. They argue Prior was right about the scope and limits of the redundancy theory and that the line he drew between those uses of ‘true’ which are and are not susceptible to treatment via redundancy serves to distinguish two important and mutually irreducible types of tru…Read more
  •  359
    Applying the concept of pain
    Iyyun 52 (July): 290-300. 2003.
    This paper reaches the conclusion that, while there are ordinary cases in which the pretending possibility is reasonable, these cases always contain some element that makes it reasonable. This will be the element we ask for when we ask why pretending possibility is raised. Knowledge that someone else is in pain is a matter of eliminating the proposed element or neutralizing its pain-negating aspect.
  • Chapter 8: Thesis One
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 215-240. 2006.
  •  38
    Roman Suzuko on Situational Identity
    Sorites 15 42-49. 2004.
    This paper gives a semantical account for the (i)ordinary propositional calculus, enriched with quantifiers binding variables standing for sentences, and with an identity-function with sentences as arguments; (ii)the ordinary theory of quantification applied to the special quantifiers; and (iii)ordinary laws of identity applied to the special function. The account includes some thoughts of Roman Suszko as well as some thoughts of Wittgenstein's Tractatus.
  •  102
    Quine’s Way Out
    Analysis 36 (1): 28-37. 1975.
    As a way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes Quine has suggested: that semantical expressions such as ‘true’ and ‘true of’ be used with numerical subscripts; that when a truth locution T is applied to a sentence S, the subscript on T is greater than any within S; otherwise, the result of applying T to S is ill formed. A problem is that this introduces infinitely many semantical primitives. The paper suggests a way around the problem. The paper raises a further problem, leaving it open whet…Read more
  •  16
    Austin and perception
    Acta Analytica 16 (27): 169-193. 2001.
    Some of Austin's general statements about the doctrines of sense-datum philosophy are reviewed. It is concluded that Austin thought that in these doctrines "directly see" is given a new but inadequately explained and defined use. Were this so, the philosophical use of "directly see" would lack a definite sense and this would correspondingly affect the doctrines. They would lack definite truth-value. Against this, it is argued that the philosopher's use of "directly see" does not support Austin's…Read more
  • Chapter 6: Arithmetic and Necessity
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 159-182. 2006.
  •  55
    Nagel, Internalism, and Relativism
    Journal of Philosophical Research 1990 310-319. 1990.
    In this paper we give (1) a new interpretation to Nagel’s THE POSSIBILITY OF ALTRUISM and (2) use that interpretation to show that internalism and anti-realism are compatible, despite appearances to the contrary.
  •  96
    What is a second order theory committed to?
    Erkenntnis 20 (1). 1983.
    The paper argues that no second order theory is ontologically commited to anything beyond what its individual variables range over.
  •  28
    Do we need models?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (3): 414-422. 1987.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a nondenotational semantics for first-order languages which will match one for one each distribution of truth-values available in terms of a denotational semantics.
  •  123
    Is heaven a possible world?
    with Douglas Erlandson
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (1). 1981.
    The goal of theodicy is to show how God could create our world with all its evil. This paper argues that the theodicist can achieve her goal only if she gives up one of these three propositions: (1) evil does not exist in heaven; (2) heaven is better than the present world; (3) heaven is a possible world. Second, it is argued that the theodicist can reject (3) without giving up her belief that heaven exists, so that (3) is her best alternative.
  •  31
    More on assertion and belief
    Philosophical Studies 22 (1-2). 1971.
    In an earlier paper Sayward argued that a speaker could not make an assertion by uttering a sentence of form “p, but I believe not-p” given that the speaker spoke honestly and literally. Robert Imlay criticized some things said in that earlier paper. This paper responds to those criticisms.
  •  39
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophishe Studien 41 150-173. 1991.
    A case against Prior’s theory of propositions goes thus: (1) everyday propositional generalizations are not substitutional; (2) Priorean quantifications are not objectual; (3) quantifications are substitutional if not objectual; (4) thus, Priorean quantifications are substitutional; (5) thus that Priorean quantifications are not ontologically committed to propositions provides no basis for a similar claim about our everyday propositional generalizations. Prior agrees with (1) and (2). He rejects…Read more
  •  89
    The Province of Logic
    Analysis 36 (1): 47-48. 1975.
    Quine criticizes Strawson’s account of the province of logic. Robert Hadley proposes a refutation of Quine. This paper proposes a refutation of Hadley.
  •  381
    What’s So Special About Sentences?
    Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 28 (4): 409-25. 1995.
    This paper is a discussion of Frege's maxim that it is only in the context of a sentence that a word has a meaning. Quine reads the maxim as saying that the sentence is the fundamental unit of significance. Dummett rejects this as a truism. But it is not a truism since it stands in opposition to a conception of meaning held by John Locke and others. The maxim denies that a word has a sense independently of any sentence in which it occurs. Dummett says this denial is inconsistent with the fact th…Read more
  •  266
    Quine’s way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes (Ways of Paradox, pp. 9-10) is criticized. The criticism is based on three premises: (1) no learnable language has infinitely many semantical primitives; (2) any language of which Quine’s theory is true has infinitely many semantical primitives; (3) English is a learnable language. The conclusion drawn is that Quine’s theory is not true of English.
  •  123
    Determining whether the law of excluded middle requires bivalence depends upon whether we are talking about sentences or propositions. If we are talking about sentences, neither side has a decisive case. If we are talking of propositions, there is a strong argument on the side of those who say the excluded middle does require bivalence. I argue that all challenges to this argument can be met.
  •  51
    Is English inconsistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3). 1980.
    The significance of the semantical paradoxes for natural languages is examined. If Tarski’s reflections on the issue are correct, English is inconsistent. Paul Ziff responds to Tarskian reflections by arguing to the conclusion that no natural language is or can be inconsistent. The authors reject Ziff’s argument, but they defend something similar to its conclusion: no language, natural or otherwise, is or can be inconsistent in the way that Tarski holds languages capable of formulating the Epime…Read more
  •  18
    Should persons be sacrificed for the general welfare?
    Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (2): 149-152. 1982.
    It is argued that Robert Nozick is wrong in asserting that persons should not be sacrificed for the general welfare.
  •  13
    The Internal/External Question
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 47 (1): 31-41. 1994.
  •  3
    Replies to Commentaries
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 (1): 369-386. 2006.
  •  86
    A defense of mill on other minds
    Dialectica 57 (3). 2003.
    This paper seeks to explain why the argument from analogy seems strong to an analogist such as Mill and weak to the skeptic. The inference from observed behavior to the existence of feelings, sensations, etc., in other subjects is justified, but its justification depends on taking observed behavior and feelings, sensations, and so on, to be not merely correlated, but connected. It is claimed that this is what Mill had in mind.