•  4
    Prior's Theory of Propositions
    Analysis 37 (3): 104-112. 1977.
  •  78
    Mathematical Relativism
    with Hugly Philip and Sayward Charles
    History and Philosophy of Logic 10 (1): 53-65. 1989.
    We set out a doctrine about truth for the statements of mathematics?a doctrine which we think is a worthy competitor to realist views in the philosophy of mathematics?and argue that this doctrine, which we shall call ?mathematical relativism?, withstands objections better than do other non-realist accounts
  •  28
    Do we need models?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (3): 414-422. 1987.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a nondenotational semantics for first-order languages which will match one for one each distribution of truth-values available in terms of a denotational semantics.
  •  118
    Is heaven a possible world?
    with Douglas Erlandson
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (1). 1981.
    The goal of theodicy is to show how God could create our world with all its evil. This paper argues that the theodicist can achieve her goal only if she gives up one of these three propositions: (1) evil does not exist in heaven; (2) heaven is better than the present world; (3) heaven is a possible world. Second, it is argued that the theodicist can reject (3) without giving up her belief that heaven exists, so that (3) is her best alternative.
  •  31
    More on assertion and belief
    Philosophical Studies 22 (1-2). 1971.
    In an earlier paper Sayward argued that a speaker could not make an assertion by uttering a sentence of form “p, but I believe not-p” given that the speaker spoke honestly and literally. Robert Imlay criticized some things said in that earlier paper. This paper responds to those criticisms.
  •  37
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophishe Studien 41 150-173. 1991.
    A case against Prior’s theory of propositions goes thus: (1) everyday propositional generalizations are not substitutional; (2) Priorean quantifications are not objectual; (3) quantifications are substitutional if not objectual; (4) thus, Priorean quantifications are substitutional; (5) thus that Priorean quantifications are not ontologically committed to propositions provides no basis for a similar claim about our everyday propositional generalizations. Prior agrees with (1) and (2). He rejects…Read more
  •  94
    What is a second order theory committed to?
    Erkenntnis 20 (1). 1983.
    The paper argues that no second order theory is ontologically commited to anything beyond what its individual variables range over.
  •  251
    Quine’s way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes (Ways of Paradox, pp. 9-10) is criticized. The criticism is based on three premises: (1) no learnable language has infinitely many semantical primitives; (2) any language of which Quine’s theory is true has infinitely many semantical primitives; (3) English is a learnable language. The conclusion drawn is that Quine’s theory is not true of English.
  •  123
    Determining whether the law of excluded middle requires bivalence depends upon whether we are talking about sentences or propositions. If we are talking about sentences, neither side has a decisive case. If we are talking of propositions, there is a strong argument on the side of those who say the excluded middle does require bivalence. I argue that all challenges to this argument can be met.
  •  46
    Is English inconsistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3). 1980.
    The significance of the semantical paradoxes for natural languages is examined. If Tarski’s reflections on the issue are correct, English is inconsistent. Paul Ziff responds to Tarskian reflections by arguing to the conclusion that no natural language is or can be inconsistent. The authors reject Ziff’s argument, but they defend something similar to its conclusion: no language, natural or otherwise, is or can be inconsistent in the way that Tarski holds languages capable of formulating the Epime…Read more
  •  89
    The Province of Logic
    Analysis 36 (1): 47-48. 1975.
    Quine criticizes Strawson’s account of the province of logic. Robert Hadley proposes a refutation of Quine. This paper proposes a refutation of Hadley.
  •  372
    What’s So Special About Sentences?
    Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 28 (4): 409-25. 1995.
    This paper is a discussion of Frege's maxim that it is only in the context of a sentence that a word has a meaning. Quine reads the maxim as saying that the sentence is the fundamental unit of significance. Dummett rejects this as a truism. But it is not a truism since it stands in opposition to a conception of meaning held by John Locke and others. The maxim denies that a word has a sense independently of any sentence in which it occurs. Dummett says this denial is inconsistent with the fact th…Read more
  •  17
    Should persons be sacrificed for the general welfare?
    Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (2): 149-152. 1982.
    It is argued that Robert Nozick is wrong in asserting that persons should not be sacrificed for the general welfare.
  •  8
    The Internal/External Question
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 47 (1): 31-41. 1994.
  •  85
    A defense of mill on other minds
    Dialectica 57 (3). 2003.
    This paper seeks to explain why the argument from analogy seems strong to an analogist such as Mill and weak to the skeptic. The inference from observed behavior to the existence of feelings, sensations, etc., in other subjects is justified, but its justification depends on taking observed behavior and feelings, sensations, and so on, to be not merely correlated, but connected. It is claimed that this is what Mill had in mind.
  • Chapter 2: Notes to Grundlagen
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 45-72. 2006.
  •  766
    Quine and his Critics on Truth-Functionality and Extensionality
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 16 (1): 45-63. 2007.
    Quine argues that if sentences that are set theoretically equivalent are interchangeable salva veritate, then all transparent operators are truth-functional. Criticisms of this argument fail to take into account the conditional character of the conclusion. Quine also argues that, for any person P with minimal logical acuity, if ‘belief’ has a sense in which it is a transparent operator, then, in that sense of the word, P believes everything if P believes anything. The suggestion is made that he …Read more
  •  3
    Replies to Commentaries
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 (1): 369-386. 2006.
  •  68
    Quine's relativism
    Ratio 3 (2): 142-149. 1990.
    A doctrine that occurs intermittently in Quine’s work is that there is no extra-theoretic truth. This paper explores this doctrine, and argues that on its best interpretation it is inconsistent with three views Quine also accepts: bivalence, mathematical Platonism, and the disquotational account of truth.
  •  161
    A problem about conversational implicature
    Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (1). 1979.
    Conversational implicatures are easy to grasp for the most part. But it is another matter to give a rational reconstruction of how they are grasped. We argue that Grice's attempt to do this fails. We distinguish two sorts of cases: (1) those in which we grasp the implicature by asking ourselves what would the speaker have to believe given that what he said is such as is required by the talk exchange; (2) those in which we grasp the implicature by asking ourselves why it is that what the speaker …Read more
  •  293
    Must Synonymous Predicates be Coextensive?
    Logique Et Analyse 95 (95): 430-435. 1981.
    Two cases are distinguished. In one case two predicates belong to distinct languages. A straight-forward argument is presented that the predicates might be synonymous without being coextensive. In the second case the predicates belong to the same language. Here the issue is more involved, but the same conclusion is reached.
  •  54
    Prior on Propositional Identity
    Analysis 36 (4): 182-184. 1976.
    Let A, B, C stand for sentences expressing propositions; let A be a component of C; let C A/B be just like C except for replacing some occurrence of A in C by an occurrence of B; let = be a binary connective for propositional identity read as ‘the proposition that __ is the very same proposition as …’. Then authors defend adding ‘from C = C A/B infer A = B’ to Prior’s rules for propositional identity, appearing in OBJECTS OF THOUGHT.
  •  193
    The structure of type theory
    with Stephen H. Voss
    Journal of Philosophy 77 (5): 241-259. 1980.
    Formal principals are isolated to reveal a structure embedded in a wide range of studies, each of which partitions a domain of individuals into types and categories. It is thought that any reasonable theory of types should include these principles.
  •  571
    What Truth is there in Psychological Egoism?
    Facta Philosophica 8 (1-2): 145-159. 2006.
    Psychological egoism says that a purposive action is self-interested in a certain sense. The trick is to say in what sense. On the one hand, the psychological egoist wants to avoid a thesis that can be falsified by trivial examples. On the other hand, what is wanted is a thesis that lacks vacuity. The paper’s purpose is to arrive at such a thesis and show that it is a reasonable guess with empirical content.
  •  10
    Geach on Generalization
    Dialogue 41 (2): 221-240. 2002.
    RÉSUMÉ: Il y a des objections plausibles contre une approche substitutionnelle de la généralisation, dont certaines peuvent être contrées par un appel à une version de l'approche substitutionnelle qui a été proposée par Peter Geach il y a presque quarante ans. Il n'est pas clair que la conception substitutionnelle de Geach vaille pour tous les phénomènes de généralisation, mais on s'emploie ici à montrer que c'est une conception qui est tout à fait digne de considération et qu'elle donne bel et …Read more
  •  680
    Null Sentences
    Iyyun, The Jewish Philosophical Quarterly 48 23-36. 1999.
    In Tractatus, Wittgenstein held that there are null sentences – prominently including logical truths and the truths of mathematics. He says that such sentences are without sense (sinnlos), that they say nothing; he also denies that they are nonsensical (unsinning). Surely it is what a sentence says which is true or false. So if a sentence says nothing, how can it be true or false? The paper discusses the issue.
  •  49
    Understanding sentences
    Philosophical Investigations 23 (1). 2000.
    Doubts are raised about the claim that on mastering a finite vocabulary and a finitely stated set of rules we are prepared to understand a potential infinitude of sentences. One doubt is about understanding a potential infinitude of sentences. A second doubt is about the assumption that understanding a sentence must be a matter of figuring out its meaning from an antecedent knowledge of the meaning of its words and applying rules.
  •  64
    Classical logic and truth-value gaps
    Philosophical Papers 21 (2): 141-150. 1992.
    An account of the logic of bivalent languages with truth-value gaps is given. This account is keyed to the use of tables introduced by S. C. Kleene. The account has two guiding ideas. First, that the bivalence property insures that the language satisfies classical logic. Second, that the general concepts of a valid sentence and an inconsistent sentence are, respectively, as sentences which are not false in any model and sentences which are not true in any model. What recommends this approach is …Read more