•  15
    William James, one of America’s most original philosophers and psychologists, was concerned above all with the manner in which philosophy might help people to cope with the vicissitudes of daily life. Writing around the turn of the twentieth century, James experienced firsthand, much as we do now, the impact upon individuals and communities of rapid changes in extant values, technologies, economic realities, and ways of understanding the world. He presented an enormous range of practical recomme…Read more
  •  18
    Editorial: Future Education: Schools and Universities
    Journal of Philosophy in Schools 6 (1): 1-9. 2019.
    While some may argue that universities are in a state of crisis, others claim that we are living in a post-university era; a time after universities. If there was a battle for the survival of the institution, it is over and done with. The buildings still stand. Students enrol and may attend lectures, though let’s be clear—most do not. But virtually nothing real remains. What some mistakenly take to be a university is, in actuality, an ‘uncanny’ spectral presence; ‘the nagging presence of an abse…Read more
  •  15
    Leadership and Ethics
    Bloomsbury. 2015.
    Contemporary discussions about the nature of leadership abound. But what constitutes a good leader? Are ethics and leadership even compatible? Accounts of leadership often lie at either end of an ethical spectrum: on one end are accounts that argue ethics are intrinsically linked to leadership; on the other are (Machiavellian) views that deny any such link-intrinsic or extrinsic. Leadership appears to require a normative component of virtue; otherwise 'leadership' amounts to no more than mere po…Read more
  •  15
    Michael Levine's book is the first comprehensive study of pantheism as a philosophical position. Spinoza's Ethics, finished in 1675, has long been seen as the most complete attempt at explaining and defending pantheism. Historically, however, pantheism has numerous forms and Spinoza's version is best considered as one among many variations on pantheistic themes. Levine manages to disentangle the concept from Spinoza; this book is a broad philosophical and historical survey of pantheism itself. T…Read more
  •  16
    Pantheism: A Non-Theistic Concept of Deity
    Religious Studies 32 (2): 285-286. 1994.
  •  10
    Robinson on Berkeley
    with Neil Levi
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 163-178. 1992.
  •  51
    Historical Anti-Realism
    The Monist 74 (2): 230-239. 1991.
    In “Narrative Explanations: The Case of History,” Paul A. Roth attempts to defend the legitimacy of narrative explanation in history against two central objections—the “methodological” and the “metaphysical.” Like Roth, I find the category of narrative explanation acceptable even if it is problematic, and even if the notions of “narrative,” “explanation,” and “narrative explanation” are not altogether clear. The philosophically grounded “methodological” objections to narrative explanation are of…Read more
  •  6
    Hume On Miracles
    Philosophie Et Culture: Actes du XVIIe Congrès Mondial de Philosophie 3 340-344. 1988.
  •  7
    Divine Unity and Superfluous Synonymity
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 4 (3). 1990.
  •  41
    Robinson on Berkeley
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 163-178. 1992.
  •  58
    Mediated memories
    Angelaki 11 (2). 2006.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  24
    Self-authenticating experiences of God: A reply to professor Oakes (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (2). 1984.
  •  50
    More on “does traditional theism entail pantheism?”
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 20 (1). 1986.
  •  20
    Kierkegaard: What does the subjective individual risk? (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 13 (1). 1982.
  •  77
    Hume's Abject Failure: The Argument against Miracles (review)
    Hume Studies 28 (1): 161-167. 2002.
    This book is divided into two parts. The first is Earman's harsh critique of Hume's essay and its conclusions. The second part of the book contains selections from primary texts of Locke, Spinoza, Clarke, and others, along with the text "Of Miracles," recording changes that Hume made. There is little in the way of explanation, a single paragraph in the preface, as to why these texts have been selected. Presumably, Earman sees each of these as containing something significant to contribute to the…Read more
  •  70
    Philosophers often distinguish in some way between two senses of life's meaning. Paul Edwards terms these a ‘cosmic’ and ‘terrestrial’ sense. The cosmic sense is that of an overall purpose of which our lives are a part and in terms of which our lives must be understood and our purposes and interests arranged. This overall purpose is often identified with God's divine scheme, but the two need not necessarily be equated. The terrestrial sense of meaning is the meaning people find in their own live…Read more
  •  27
    ‘Can we speak literally of God?’: MICHAEL P. LEVINE
    Religious Studies 21 (1): 53-59. 1985.
    I shall argue that the question ‘Can we speak literally of God?’ is fundamentally an epistemological question concerning whether we can know that God exists. If and only if we can know that God can exist can we know that we can speak literally of God
  •  44
    Pantheism, Ethics and Ecology
    Environmental Values 3 (2). 1994.
    Pantheism is a metaphysical and religious position. Broadly defined it is the view that (1) "God is everything and everything is God ... the world is either identical with God or in some way a self-expression of his nature" (H.P. Owen). Similarly, it is the view that (2) everything that exists constitutes a 'unity' and this all-inclusive unity is in some sense divine (A. MacIntyre). I begin with an account of what the pantheist's ethical position is formally likely to be (e.g. objectivist etc.).…Read more
  •  20
    Berkeley's theocentric mentalism: Pantheism? (review)
    Sophia 26 (1): 30-41. 1987.
  •  26
    Museums and the Nostalgic Self
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 79 77-94. 2016.
    The first part of this essay asks: What is the function, purpose and value of a museum? Has any museologist or philosopher given a credible account of philosophical problems associated with museums? Is there any set of properties shared by the diverse entities called museums? Overgeneralization is the principal problem here. The essay then examines a central kind of museum experience; one that invokes and relies upon nostalgia. I argue that the attraction of museums are varied but are best expla…Read more
  • "Entry on" Miracles
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  30
    Transcendence in theism and pantheism
    Sophia 31 (3): 89-123. 1992.
  •  21
    Let us follow Robert Oakes in describing a self-authenticating experience of God as one that ‘would have the epistemic uniqueness of guaranteeing –all by itself – its veridicality to the person who had it.’ The idea that there could be self-authenticating experiences of God has been criticized often in recent years. It seems that the only experiences that could be self-authenticating are those about one's own current psychological states. Nevertheless, the individual who claims to have such an e…Read more
  •  36
    In this paper I dispute Eliot Deutsch's claim [See Deutsch, Eliot (1996) Self-deception: a comparative study, in: Roger T. Ames and Wimal Dissanayake (Eds) Self and Deception: a cross-cultural enquiry (Albany, State University of New York Press), pp. 315-326] that examining self-deception from the perspective of non-Western traditions (i.e. how it is understood in those cultures) can help us to better understand the nature of the phenomenon in one's own culture. Although the claim appears to be …Read more