Charlottesville, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
Philosophy of Mind
Areas of Interest
Epistemology
Philosophy of Mind
  •  70
    Consciousness, experience, and justification
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1): 1-28. 2002.
    I think it is important to try to make sense of these thoughts concerning the justificatory role of experiences, for I suspect that we are losing the ability to see why philosophers have traditionally been attracted to such thoughts. Coherentism and reliabilism, perhaps the two most currently popular theories of epistemic justification, appear simply to reject the idea that experiences can justify beliefs. Thus according to coherentism, the view that ‘a belief is justified by its coherence with …Read more
  •  13
    Why Colours
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198): 68-75. 2000.
  •  24
    Risks and Wrongs
    Philosophical Review 104 (3): 477. 1995.
  •  129
    A Defense of McDowell’s Response to the Sceptic
    Acta Analytica 29 (1): 43-59. 2014.
    Crispin Wright argues that John McDowell’s use of disjunctivism to respond to the sceptic misses the point of the sceptic’s argument, for disjunctivism is a thesis about the differing metaphysical natures of veridical and nonveridical experiences, whereas the sceptic’s point is that our beliefs are unjustified because veridical and nonveridical experiences can be phenomenally indistinguishable. In this paper, I argue that McDowell is responsive to the sceptic’s focus on phenomenology, for the po…Read more
  •  50
    Why Pains are Mental Objects
    Journal of Philosophy 92 (6): 303. 1995.
  •  162
    The intuitive case for naïve realism
    Philosophical Explorations 20 (1): 106-122. 2017.
    Naïve realism, the view that perceptual experiences are irreducible relations between subjects and external objects, has intuitive appeal, but this intuitive appeal is sometimes thought to be undermined by the possibility of certain kinds of hallucinations. In this paper, I present the intuitive case for naïve realism, and explain why this intuitive case is not undermined by the possibility of such hallucinations. Specifically, I present the intuitive case for naïve realism as arguing that the o…Read more
  •  19
    Consciousness, Experience, and Justification
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1): 1-28. 2002.
    A belief must have justification if it is to count as knowledge. And it is a commonplace thought that in certain circumstances experiences can serve as justifications for beliefs. Moreover, many have thought that there is something distinctive about the wayin which experiences justify beliefs, and that there is something distinctive about experiences which accounts for the distinctive way in which they justify beliefs. In this paper, I seek to elucidate views about experience and justification t…Read more