•  228
    The power of the hexagon
    Logica Universalis 6 (1-2): 1-43. 2012.
    The hexagon of opposition is an improvement of the square of opposition due to Robert Blanché. After a short presentation of the square and its various interpretations, we discuss two important problems related with the square: the problem of the I-corner and the problem of the O-corner. The meaning of the notion described by the I-corner does not correspond to the name used for it. In the case of the O-corner, the problem is not a wrong-name problem but a no-name problem and it is not clear wha…Read more
  • Contemporary Brazilian research in logic part II
    with Arthur Buchsbaum, Tarcisio Pequeno, A. General, and Newton Ca da Costa
    Logique Et Analyse 40 3. 1997.
  •  148
    Sentence, proposition and identity
    Synthese 154 (3). 2007.
    In this paper we discuss the distinction between sentence and proposition from the perspective of identity. After criticizing Quine, we discuss how objects of logical languages are constructed, explaining what is Kleene’s congruence—used by Bourbaki with his square—and Paul Halmos’s view about the difference between formulas and objects of the factor structure, the corresponding boolean algebra, in case of classical logic. Finally we present Patrick Suppes’s congruence approach to the notion of …Read more
  •  60
    Preface: Is logic universal? (review)
    Logica Universalis 4 (2): 161-162. 2010.
  •  48
    Disentangling Contradiction from Contrariety via Incompatibility
    Logica Universalis 10 (2-3): 157-170. 2016.
    Contradiction is often confused with contrariety. We propose to disentangle contrariety from contradiction using the hexagon of opposition, providing a clear and distinct characterization of three notions: contrariety, contradiction, incompatibility. At the same time, this hexagonal structure describes and explains the relations between them.
  •  69
    Idempotent Full Paraconsistent Negations are not Algebraizable
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (1): 135-139. 1998.
    Using methods of abstract logic and the theory of valuation, we prove that there is no paraconsistent negation obeying the law of double negation and such that $\neg(a\wedge\neg a)$ is a theorem which can be algebraized by a technique similar to the Tarski-Lindenbaum technique.
  • A Logical Analysis Of Singular Terms
    Sorites 10 6-14. 1999.
    We analyse the behaviour of definite descriptions and proper names terms in mathematical logic. We show that in formal arithmetic, wether some axioms are fixed or not, proper names cannot be considered rigid designators and have the same behaviour as definite descriptions. In set theory, sometimes two names for the same object are introduced. It seems that this can be explained by the notion of meaning. The meaning of such proper names can be considered as fuzzy sets of equivalent co-designative…Read more
  •  37
    Théorie legislative de la négation pure
    Logique Et Analyse 147 (148): 209-225. 1994.
  •  184
    The relativity and universality of logic
    Synthese 192 (7): 1939-1954. 2015.
    After recalling the distinction between logic as reasoning and logic as theory of reasoning, we first examine the question of relativity of logic arguing that the theory of reasoning as any other science is relative. In a second part we discuss the emergence of universal logic as a general theory of logical systems, making comparison with universal algebra and the project of mathesis universalis. In a third part we critically present three lines of research connected to universal logic: logical …Read more
  •  52
    13 Questions about universal logic
    Bulletin of the Section of Logic 35 (2/3): 133-150. 2006.
  •  51
    Many-valued and Kripke semantics
    In Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.), The Age of Alternative Logics, Springer. pp. 89--101. 2006.
  •  48
    BookReview
    Studia Logica 100 (3): 653-657. 2012.
  • Overclassical logic
    with Newton Ca da Costa
    Logique Et Analyse 157 31-44. 1997.
  • For several years I have been developing a general theory of logics that I have called Universal Logic. In this article I will try to describe how I was led to this theory and how I have progressively conceived it, starting my researches about ten years ago in Paris in paraconsistent logic and the broadening my horizons, pursuing my researches in Brazil, Poland and the USA
  • We discuss Sengupta's argumentation according to which Frege was wrong identifying reference with truth-value.After stating various possible interpretations of Frege's principle of substitution, we show that there is no coherent interpretation under which Sengupta's argumentation is valid.Finally we try to show how Frege's distinction can work in the context of modern mathematics and how modern logic grasps it
  •  56
    of implication and generalization rules have a close relationship, for which there is a key idea for clarifying how they are connected: varying objects. Varying objects trace how generalization rules are used along a demonstration in an axiomatic calculus. Some ways for introducing implication and for generalization are presented here, taking into account some basic properties that calculi can have.
  •  82
    Truth as a Mathematical Object
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1): 31-46. 2010.
    Neste artigo, discutimos em que sentido a verdade é considerada como um objeto matemático na lógica proposicional. Depois de esclarecer como este conceito é usado na lógica clássica, através das noções de tabela de verdade, de função de verdade, de bivaloração, examinamos algumas generalizações desse conceito nas lógicas não clássicas: semânticas matriciais multi-valoradas com três ou quatro valores, semântica bivalente não veritativa, semânticas dos mundos possiveis de Kripke. DOI:10.5007/1808-…Read more
  • Paraconsistent Logic!
    Sorites 17 17-25. 2006.
    We answer Slater's argument according to which paraconsistent logic is a result of a verbal confusion between «contradictories» and «subcontraries». We show that if such notions are understood within classical logic, the argument is invalid, due to the fact that most paraconsistent logics cannot be translated into classical logic. However we prove that if such notions are understood from the point of view of a particular logic, a contradictory forming function in this logic is necessarily a clas…Read more
  •  32
    Semantic computations of truth based on associations already learned
    with Patrick Suppes
    Journal of Applied Logic 2 (4): 457-467. 2004.
  •  635
    La Pointure du Symbole (edited book)
    Petra. 2014.
    Dans un texte désormais célèbre, Ferdinand de Saussure insiste sur l’arbitraire du signe dont il vante les qualités. Toutefois il s’avère que le symbole, signe non arbitraire, dans la mesure où il existe un rapport entre ce qui représente et ce qui est représenté, joue un rôle fondamental dans la plupart des activités humaines, qu’elles soient scientifiques, artistiques ou religieuses. C’est cette dimension symbolique, sa portée, son fonctionnement et sa signification dans des domaines aussi var…Read more
  •  74
    Logic may be simple. Logic, congruence and algebra
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 5 (n/a): 129-147. 1997.
    This paper is an attempt to clear some philosophical questions about the nature of logic by setting up a mathematical framework. The notion of congruence in logic is defined. A logical structure in which there is no non-trivial congruence relation, like some paraconsistent logics, is called simple. The relations between simplicity, the replacement theorem and algebraization of logic are studied (including MacLane-Curry’s theorem and a discussion about Curry’s algebras). We also examine how these…Read more
  •  23
    Carnot's logic
    with Newton Ca da Costa
    Bulletin of the Section of Logic 22 (3): 98-105. 1993.
  •  62
    A new four-valued approach to modal logic
    Logique Et Analyse 54 (213): 109. 2011.
  •  44
    The New Rising of the Square of Opposition
    In J.-Y. Beziau & Dale Jacquette (eds.), Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition, Birkhäuser. pp. 3--19. 2012.