•  180
    Doing what is best
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (199): 208-226. 2000.
  •  16
    Choices (review)
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 30 (1): 197-207. 1987.
  •  33
    Preface
    with Johannes Brandl and Wolfgang Gombocz
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 40 1-2. 1991.
  •  26
    Schwierige metaethik
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 70 (1): 241-252. 2006.
  •  135
    Normative Practical Reasoning
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1). 2001.
    Practical reasoning is a process of reasoning that concludes in an intention. One example is reasoning from intending an end to intending what you believe is a necessary means: 'I will leave the next buoy to port; in order to do that I must tack; so I'll tack', where the first and third sentences express intentions and the second sentence a belief. This sort of practical reasoning is supported by a valid logical derivation, and therefore seems uncontrovertible. A more contentious example is norm…Read more
  •  175
    Desiring the truth and nothing but the truth
    Noûs 43 (2): 193-213. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  16
    Antikritische Bemerkungen
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 32 (1): 197-204. 1988.
  •  125
  •  105
    One of the guiding ideas of virtue epistemology is to look at epistemological issue through the lens of practical philosophy. The Gettier Problem is a case in point. Virtue epistemologists, like Sosa and Greco, see the shortcoming in a Gettier scenario as a shortcoming from which performances in general can suffer. In this paper I raise some doubts about the success of this project. Looking more closely at practical philosophy, will, I argue, show that virtue epistemology misconceives the signif…Read more
  •  572
    Ewing's Problem
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 3 (1): 0-0. 2007.
    Two plausible claims seem to be inconsistent with each other. One is the idea that if one reasonably believes that one ought to fi, then indeed, on pain of acting irrationally, one ought to fi. The other is the view that we are fallible with respect to our beliefs about what we ought to do. Ewing’s Problem is how to react to this apparent inconsistency. I reject two easy ways out. One is Ewing’s own solution to his problem, which is to introduce two different notions of ought. The other is the v…Read more
  •  3
    Critical Notice
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (2): 347-367. 1996.
    Critical notice of Smith, Michael, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994) pp. xiii, 226, A$49.95 (cloth), A$21.95 (paper).
  •  14
    Preface
    with Johannes Brandl and Wolfgang Gombocz
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 40 1-2. 1991.
  •  66
    Two accounts of objective reasons (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2). 2003.
    GE Moore vehemently defended the view that what actually happens and not what we, even reasonably, expect to happen, determines what we ought to do. ‘The only possible reason that can justify any action’, Moore writes, ‘is that by it the greatest possible amount of what is good absolutely should be realized’. Moore is an objectivist about reasons and duties: The world and not our view of it gives us reasons to act; the way the world is, and not the way we think it is, determines what we ought to…Read more