•  1204
    Dilemmas of Rawlsian Opportunity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (1): 1-24. 2010.
    John Rawls's repeated assertions that the basic structure of society creates profound and inevitable differences in life prospects for people born in different starting places seems to contradict his assertions that, under fair equality of opportunity, a person's life prospects would not be affected by class of origin for those similarly endowed and motivated. This seeming contradiction seems to be resolved by Rawls's apparent belief that class of origin inevitably affects motivation. This recon…Read more
  •  35
    The Fallacy Of Philanthropy
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1): 29-65. 2002.
    Should we stop spending money on things we do not really need and send the money instead to groups that aid victims of absolute poverty? Garrett Cullity and Peter Unger have given renewed vigor to the well known argument by Peter Singer that we should do this. Like Singer, Cullity and Unger compare our duties to the poor to our duties when we encounter a victim of calamity, such as a child in danger of drowning. Singer and Unger tell us what to do and why we must do it; most starkly, Unger gives…Read more
  • Free Will as Ultimate Responsibility
    American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (3): 205-211. 1978.
  •  867
    Abortion and the Morality of Nurturance
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (4). 1991.
    Most discussion of the morality of abortion assume the central issue is whether the fetus is a person. I disagree. The central issue is better understood as whether the fetus is one's *baby* whom one has a duty to nurture (babies need not be persons). Understanding the central issue as centering on duties to nurture one's children allows us better to understand both liberal and conservative views about abortion.
  •  54
    Autonomy and free expression
    Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (2): 97-104. 1994.
  •  293
    Patriotism is like racism
    Ethics 101 (1): 144-150. 1990.
  •  310
    Does “possible” ever mean “logically possible”?
    Philosophia 8 (2-3): 389-403. 1978.
    Are skeptical arguments invalid because they trade on an ambiguity of the word "possible," asserting that it is possible that our experiences are not of anything outside our own minds and concluding that it is not certain that there is an external world outside our own minds? It is sometimes asserted that such arguments invalidly trade on an ambiguity of "possible" where the premise is true only in the sense "logically possible" while the inference is valid only in the sense "empirically possibl…Read more
  •  55
    Consequentialism and History
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (3). 1989.
    John Stuart Mill wrote in the opening chapter of Utilitarianism, ‘A test of right and wrong must be the means, one would think, of ascertaining what is right or wrong,’ thus explaining why he thought the work to follow was practically important. In Chapter 3, ‘On the Ultimate Sanction of the Principle of Utility,’ he answers the question, ‘What are the motives to obey the principle of utility?’ This principle is presented as a morality to be adopted. Yet before the nineteenth century was over He…Read more
  •  628
    Against competitive equal opportunity
    Journal of Social Philosophy 26 (3): 59-73. 1995.
    Competitive opportunity assumes limited positions of advantage. Making competitive opportunity equal without expanding opportunity would delay socialization for diminished expectations but have no advantages, thus possibly making a bad situation worse. Equal opportunity worth fighting for would be opportunity available to all non-competitively.
  •  19
  •  43
    Why be Moral?
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 700. 1992.
  •  72
  •  26
    Can a Partisan Be a Moralist?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (1). 1990.
  •  964
    The Fallacy of Philanthropy
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1). 2002.
    Global poverty, hunger, and lack of access to save water raise problems of how to organize human society so that everyone's needs can be met. Philanthropic proposals, such as Peter Singer's and Peter Unger's, are based on a false analogy to duties of rescue and encourage philanthropic responses, thus closing the discourse to discussion of the causes and remedies of poverty. Radical criticism of capitalist social structures are put off the table, and this is a profound error.
  •  31
  •  1308
    Distributive justice, defined as justice in distribution of income and wealth, is impossible. Income and wealth are distributed either unequally or equally. If unequally, then those with less are unjustly subject to social contempt. But equal distribution is impossible because it is inconsistent with bargaining to advance our own good. Hence justice in distribution of income and wealth is impossible. More generally, societies where social relations are mediated by money are necessarily unjust, a…Read more