•  93
    Systematicity: The Nature of Science
    Oxford University Press USA. 2013.
    In Systematicity, Paul Hoyningen-Huene answers the question "What is science?" by proposing that scientific knowledge is primarily distinguished from other forms of knowledge, especially everyday knowledge, by being more systematic. "Science" is here understood in the broadest possible sense, encompassing not only the natural sciences but also mathematics, the social sciences, and the humanities. The author develops his thesis in nine dimensions in which it is claimed that science is more system…Read more
  •  89
    Context of discovery versus context of justification and Thomas Kuhn
    In Jutta Schickore & Friedrich Steinle (eds.), Revisiting Discovery and Justification, Springer. pp. 119--131. 2006.
  •  73
    Der zusammenhang Von wissenschaftsphilosophie, wissenschaftsgeschichte und wissenschaftssoziologie in der theorie Thomas Kuhns
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 22 (1): 43-59. 1991.
    Summary The paper deals with the interrelations among philosophy, sociology, and historiography of science in Thomas Kuhn's theory of scientific development. First, historiography of science provides the basis for both philosophy and sociology of science in the sense that the fundamental questions of both disciplines depend on the principles of the form of historiography employed. Second, the fusion of sociology and philosophy of science, as advocated by Kuhn, is discussed. This fusion consists …Read more
  •  72
    Reference, ontological replacement and Neo-Kantianism: a reply to Sankey
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2): 203-209. 2009.
    Contrary to Sankey’s central assumption, incommensurability does not imply incomparability of content, nor threaten scientific realism by challenging the rationality of theory comparison. Moreover, Sankey equivocates between reference to specific entities by statements used to test theories and reference to kinds by theories themselves. This distinction helps identify and characterize the genuine threat that incommensurability poses to realism, which is ontological discontinuity as evidenced in …Read more
  •  71
    Feyerabend's Early Philosophy
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 31 (2): 363-375. 2000.
  •  69
    Thomas S. Kuhn
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 28 (2): 235-256. 1997.
  •  66
    Tensions between science and society
    Axiomathes 19 (4): 417-424. 2009.
    What are the “costs” of science besides its expected benefits? Specifically, how “tense” does the relation between science and society become in the light of the ever-increasing pressure of the latter on the former? In this paper I am going to discus the increasing global inequality deriving from phenomena such as the “brain drain” and from the problems relative to the relationship between ethics and science. I will conclude by considering the tension that arises out of the disciplinary structur…Read more
  •  58
    On naturalizing Kuhn’s essential tension
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1): 215-218. 2011.
  •  51
    Philosophy of Science: Between the Natural Sciences, the Social Sciences, and the Humanities (edited book)
    with Antonio Piccolomini D’Aragona, Martin Carrier, Roger Deulofeu, Axel Gelfert, Jens Harbecke, Lara Huber, Peter Hucklenbroich, Ludger Jansen, Elizaveta Kostrova, Keizo Matsubara, Anne Sophie Meincke, Andrea Reichenberger, Kian Salimkhani, and Javier Suárez
    Springer Verlag. 2018.
    This broad and insightful book presents current scholarship in important subfields of philosophy of science and addresses an interdisciplinary and multidisciplinary readership. It groups carefully selected contributions into the four fields of I) philosophy of physics, II) philosophy of life sciences, III) philosophy of social sciences and values in science, and IV) philosophy of mathematics and formal modeling. Readers will discover research papers by Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Keizo Matsubara, Kian…Read more
  •  49
    More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on Proto-Structure
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4): 610-632. 2006.
    The paper contains two yet unknown letters that Feyerabend wrote to Kuhn in 1960 or 1961 on a draft of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In these letters, Feyerabend criticises both details of Kuhn's book and its general direction. The letters anticipate many of the arguments that were put forward in the public controversy against Kuhn's position, including some of the (numerous) misunderstandings. Feyerabend's assertions and arguments are very characteristic of his position in the early …Read more
  •  48
    Replies
    Synthese 196 (3): 907-928. 2019.
    In this article, I reply to the preceding articles by Naomi Oreskes, Chrysostomos Mantzavinos, Brad Wray, Sarah Green, Alexander Bird, and Timothy Lyons. These articles contain a number of objections and suggestions concerning systematicity theory, as developed in my book ystematicity: The Nature of Science.
  •  47
    Münsteraner Memorandum Heilpraktiker. Die Thesen des „Münsteraner Kreises“ zu einer Neuregelung des Heilpraktikerwesens
    with Manfred Anlauf, Norbert Aust, Hans-Werner Bertelsen, Juliane Boscheinen, Edzard Ernst, Daniel R. Friedrich, Natalie Grams, Jutta Hübner, Peter Hucklenbroich, Heiner Raspe, Jan-Ole Reichardt, Norbert Schmacke, Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Oliver R. Scholz, Jochen Taupitz, and Christian Weymayr
    Ethik in der Medizin 29 (4): 334-342. 2017.
  •  43
    Idealist Elements In Thomas Kuhn'S Philosophy Of Science
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 6 (October): 393-401. 1989.
  •  42
    This paper deals with the following questions: What features of modern natural science are responsible for the fact that, of all forms of science, this form is technologically exploitable? The three notions: concept of nature, epistemic ideal, and experiment, suggest the most important components of my answer. I will argue, first, that only the peculiar interplay of the modern concept of nature with an epistemic ideal attuned to it can cast experiment in the specific, highly central role it play…Read more
  •  38
    Incommensurability and Related Matters (edited book)
    Kluwer Academic Publishers. 2001.
    Incommensurability and Related Matters draws together some of the most distinguished contributors to the critical literature on the problem of the incommensurability of scientific theories. It addresses all the various problems raised by the problem of incommensurability, such as meaning change, reference of theoretical terms, scientific realism and anti-realism, rationality of theory choice, cognitive aspects of conceptual change, as well as exploring the broader implications of incommensurabil…Read more
  •  34
    Niels Bohr's argument for the irreducibility of biology to physics
    In Jan Faye & Henry J. Folse (eds.), Niels Bohr and Contemporary Philosophy, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 231--255. 1994.
  •  28
  •  26
    Précis zu Systematicity. The Nature of Science
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 69 (2): 225-229. 2015.
  •  24
    Incommensurability, Realism, and Meta-Incommensurability
    Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 12 (3): 447-465. 1997.
    The essay begins with a detailed consideration of the introduction of incommensurability by Feyerabend in 1962 which exposes several historically inaccurate claims about incommensurability. Section 2 is a coneise argument against causal theories of reference as used as arguments against incommensurability. We object to this strategy because it begs the question by presupposing realism. Section 3 introduces and discusses a hypothesis that w'e call meta-incommensurability which provides the reason…Read more
  •  23
    Irrationality in Scientific Development?
    Philosophy Study 3 (5). 2013.
    The paper discusses several wide-spread misunderstandings of Kuhn’s theory of scientific development, most prominently the ascription that he conceives of scientific development as irrational. The core of this ascription is an assessment of incommensurability as implying the lack of any rational possibility of theory comparison. This is supposed to be due to Gestalt switches and a quasi-religious element of conversion in theory change. Accordingly, scientific revolutions cannot be a serious matt…Read more
  •  19
    A Note on the Concept of Game
    In Gregor Betz, Dirk Koppelberg, David Lüwenstein & Anna Wehofsits (eds.), Weiter Denken - Über Philosophie, Wissenschaft Und Religion, De Gruyter. pp. 205-210. 2015.
  •  19
    Is Kuhn’s “World Change through Revolutions” Comprehensible?
    Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 59 (4): 55-72. 2022.
    Kuhn’s talk of “world change through revolutions” has mostly been met with perplexity. What is it really that Kuhn wants to express in this strange way? I will first review what Kuhn exactly says on this topic. Next, I show that the world change talk is at least not inconsistent and has some initial plausibility. Then I will discuss whether “world change through revolutions” should be replaced by “change of world view”. This will show that “world change through revolutions” is motivated by a str…Read more
  •  18
    Die im Aufsatz vorgetragene Kritik am Leitmotiv von Georg Pichts Vorlesung "Der Begriff der Natur und seine Geschichte" kann wie folgt zusammengefaßt werden:1. Das für die Natur bedrohliche Handeln ist nicht primär als angewandte Naturwissenschaft, sondern als technisches Handeln zu bestimmen.2. Die Zerstörung von Natur ist nicht Ausdruck einer Wesensqualität von Wissenschaft, sondern allenfalls eine Nebenfolge ihrer Anwendung, primär aber eine Nebenfolge des technischen Handelns.3. Wissenschaft…Read more
  •  17
    The Plausibility of Thomas Kuhn’s Metaphysics
    In Pablo Melogno, Hernán Miguel & Leandro Giri (eds.), Perspectives on Kuhn: Contemporary Approaches to the Philosophy of Thomas Kuhn, Springer. pp. 139-154. 2023.
    One of the elements of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions not only confused his readers but even Kuhn himself, namely, his talk about world change. In my earlier work, I have tackled the question of Kuhn’s metaphysics from a viewpoint that was informed by Kant’s critical theoretical philosophy. Useful as this may be, in this chapter I will try a different approach. I will focus on the fact that Kuhn acted mainly as a reflective historian when he wrote Structure. Thus, he reflected on what s…Read more
  •  17
    Theorie antireduktionistischer Argumente: Fallstudie Bohr
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 39 (1-6): 194-204. 1991.