•  281
    Field on the Normative Role of Logic
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1pt3). 2009.
    I begin by summarizing the first two chapters of (Harman 1986). The first chapter stresses the importance of not confusing inference with implication and of not confusing reasoning with the sort of argument studied in deductive logic. Inference and reasoning are psychological events or processes that can be done more or less well. The sort of implication and argument studied in deductive logic have to do with relations among propositions and with structures of propositions distinguished into pre…Read more
  •  7
    The Nature of Morality. An Introduction to Ethics
    Critica 12 (36): 110-111. 1980.
  •  307
    Putnam rejects "metaphysical realism," which takes "the world" to be a single complex thing, a connected causal or explanatory order into which all facts fit. he argues that such metaphysical realism is responsible for views he finds implausible; in particular, it can lead to moral relativism when one tries to locate the place of value in the world of fact. i agree that metaphysical realism will lead a thoughtful philosopher to moral relativism, but find neither of these views implausible. in pa…Read more
  •  93
    Character
    with Maria Merritt and John Doris
    In John M. Doris (ed.), Moral Psychology Handbook, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  9
    Chapter 10. Conclusions as Total Views
    In Thought, Princeton University Press. pp. 155-172. 1973.
  •  8
    Rational insight versus general foundations
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3): 657--63. 2001.
    BonJour offers two main reasons for supposing that there is such a thing as rational insight into necessity. First, he says there are many examples in which it clearly seems that one has such insight. Second, he argues that any epistemology denying the existence of rational insight into necessity is committed to a narrow skepticism. After commenting about possible frameworks for epistemological justification, I argue against these two claims in reverse order.
  •  95
    What is distinctive about my views in epistemology? One thing is that my concern with epistemology is a concern with methodology. Furthermore, I reject psychologism about logic and reject the idea that deductive rules like modus ponens are in any way rules of inference. I accept a kind of methodological conservatism and reject methodological theories that appeal to special foundations, analytic truth, or a priori justification. Although I believe that there are significant practical aspects of t…Read more
  •  31
    What is experience made of?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (3): 356-357. 1978.
  • Cambridge University Press. 2008.
  •  95
    Philosophers sometimes approach meaning metaphorically, for example, by speaking of “grasping” meanings, as if understanding consists in getting mental hands around something.1 Philosophers say that a theory of meaning should be a theory about the meanings that people assign to expressions in their language, that to understand other people requires identifying the meanings they associate with what they are saying, and that to translate an expression of another language into your own is to find a…Read more
  •  19
    Originally published in 1990. This study argues that scepticism is an intelligible view and that the issue scepticism raises is whether or not certain sceptical hypotheses are as plausible as the ordinary views we accept. It discusses psychological concepts, definitions of knowledge, belief and hypothetic inference. Starting from ‘Is skepticism a problem for epistemology’, the book takes us through the argument for the possibility of scepticism, including looking at sense data and considering me…Read more
  •  172
    Knowledge, assumptions, lotteries
    Philosophical Issues 14 (1). 2004.
    John Hawthorne’s marvelous book contains a wealth of arguments and insights based on an impressive knowledge and understanding of contemporary discussion. We can address only a small aspect of the topic. In particular, we will offer our own answers to two questions about knowledge that he discusses.
  •  60
    Thought
    with Laurence BonJour
    Philosophical Review 84 (2): 256. 1975.
  •  12
    Précis of Part One
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 161-169. 1998.
  •  89
    Can science understand the mind?
    In George Armitage Miller & Gilbert Harman (eds.), Conceptions of the human mind: essays in honor of George A. Miller, L. Erlbaum Associates. pp. 111--121. 1993.
  •  32
    Is pain overt behavior?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1): 61-61. 1985.
  •  87
    Practical aspects of theoretical reasoning
    In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford handbook of rationality, Oxford University Press. pp. 45--56. 2004.
    Harman distinguishes between two uses of the term “logic”: as referring either to the theory of implication or to the theory of reasoning, which are quite distinct. His interest here is reasoning: a process that can modify intentions and beliefs. To a first approximation, theoretical reasoning is concerned with what to believe and practical reasoning is concerned with what to intend to do, although it is possible to have practical reasons to believe something. Practical considerations are releva…Read more
  •  15
    Chapter 3. Mental Processes
    In Thought, Princeton University Press. pp. 34-53. 1973.
  •  61
    Peacocke argues that all epistemic entitlements depend at bottom on a priori entitlements, determined by "constitutive conditions" for the application of concepts. He does not address familiar doubts about the distinction between constitutive and nonconstitutive conditions of application. In addition, Peacocke conflates issues about inference with issues about implication and proof and seriously misrepresents David Lewis' view about the content of indicative conditionals.
  •  241
    Guilt-free morality
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4 203-14. 2009.
    Here are some of the ways in which some philosophers and psychologists have taken the emotion of guilt to be essential to morality. One relatively central idea is that guilt feelings are warranted if an agent knows that he or she has acted morally wrongly. It might be said that in such a case the agent has a strong reason to feel guilt, that the agent ought to have guilt feelings, that the agent is justified in having guilt feelings and unjustified in not having guilt feelings. It might be said …Read more
  •  1
    The Simplest Hypothesis
    Critica 20 (59): 23-42. 1988.
  •  386
    Moral relativism is moral realism
    Philosophical Studies 172 (4): 855-863. 2015.
    I begin by describing my relation with Nicholas Sturgeon and his objections to things I have said about moral explanations. Then I turn to issues about moral relativism. One of these is whether a plausible version of moral relativism can be formulated as a claim about the logical form of certain moral judgments. I agree that is not a good way to think of moral relativism. Instead, I think of moral relativism as a version of moral realism. I compare moral relativism with the relativity of motion …Read more
  •  22
    Chapter 12. Inference in Memory
    In Thought, Princeton University Press. pp. 189-194. 1973.
  •  250
    The nonexistence of character traits
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2). 2000.
  •  136
    Moral particularism and transduction
    Philosophical Issues 15 (1). 2005.
    Can someone be reasonable or justified in accepting a specific moral judgment not based on the prior acceptance of a general exceptioness moral principle, where acceptance of a general principle might be tacit or implicit and might not be expressible in language? This issue is an instance of a wider issue about direct or transductive inference. Developments in statistical learning theory show that such an inference can be more effective than alternative methods using inductive generalization and…Read more