•  33
    Is World Poverty a Moral Problem for the Wealthy?
    The Journal of Ethics 8 (4): 397-408. 2004.
    This article discusses the question of poverty and wealth in light of several theses put forward by Larry Temkin. The claim that there is a sort of cosmic injustice involved when great disparities of ability or of wealth are found. He is concerned especially about disparities that are undeserved. It is agreed that this is unfortunate, but not agreed that they are unjust in a sense that supports the imposition of rectification on anyone else. Nor is poverty typically "undeserved" in the only real…Read more
  •  25
    Liberty, equality, fraternity: Harmonious or irreconcilable?
    Journal of Social Philosophy 17 (3): 20-27. 1986.
  •  30
    On honouring our parents
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (1): 65-78. 1987.
  •  54
    Inequality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 482-486. 1996.
    This book investigates the idea of inequality. According to the author, it does not address the question whether one should care about inequality nor which version is more plausible. Instead, its purpose is “to understand egalitarianism”, to “elucidate the notion of inequality”. The general thesis is that inequality is a “complex notion,” as shown by the fact that there are many different ways of measuring it. This is relentlessly detailed in a series of chapters that many will find rather hard …Read more
  •  239
    Moral problems of population
    The Monist 57 (1). 1973.
  •  50
    Pacifism—Fifty Years Later
    Philosophia 41 (4): 925-943. 2013.
    I suppose I’m writing this because of my 1965 paper on Pacifism. In that essay I argued that pacifism is self-contradictory. That’s a strong charge, and also not entirely clear. Let’s start by trying to clarify the charge and related ones.Pacifism has traditionally been understood as total opposition to violence, even the use of it in defense of oneself when under attack. I earlier maintained (in my well-known “Pacifism: A Philosophical Analysis” (Narveson, Ethics, 75:4, 259–271, 1965)) that thi…Read more
  •  107
    The Relevance of Decision Theory to Ethical Theory
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (5): 497-520. 2010.
    Morality for the purposes of this paper consists of sets of rules or principles intended for the general regulation of conduct for all. Intuitionist accounts of morality are rejected as making reasoned analysis of morals impossible. In many interactions, there is partial conflict and partial cooperation. From the general social point of view, the rational thing to propose is that we steer clear of conflict and promote cooperation. This is what it is rational to propose to reinforce, and to assis…Read more
  •  60
    Morality and non-violence
    Philosophia 8 (2-3): 447-459. 1978.
  •  92
    Egalitarians hold that some good things should, in principle, be distributed equally among all people. Which good things? Why just those and not others? Why are they to be equalized only among humans and not, say, between humans and cats? And why is the equalization to be confined within the borders of the author's State, rather than practiced over the whole human race (at least)? Those are all matters for the particular egalitarian to explain, as best he can. None, I think, can be explained sat…Read more
  •  87
    Terrorism and Pacifism
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 17 (2): 157-172. 2003.
    Pacifism and terrorism are at opposite ends of one spectrum: pacifists have too many friends; terrorists have too many enemies. The indiscriminacy robs both of any credibility. Both fail to distinguish between aggressors and their victims. Discussion of terrorism, however, is complicated by insufficient attention to the distinction between noncombatants and innocents. Just War theory relies heavily on that distinction, providing protections to noncombatants as such, without going into the furthe…Read more
  •  43
    Libertarianism, postlibertarianism, and the welfare state: Reply to Friedman
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 6 (1): 45-82. 1992.
    Jeffrey Friedman broaches a number of criticisms of Libertarianism as a conceptual basis for opposing the extensive modern welfare state, examining several variants and concluding that they are fundamentally unsupported. He opts for a “consequentialist” view of foundations. Nevertheless, he thinks that the modem welfare state is subject to effective critique along such lines. But rational contractarian individualism works and does provide foundations for libertarianism, while “consequentialism” …Read more
  •  14
    An overlooked aspect of the fairness-utility controversy
    Journal of Value Inquiry 8 (2): 124-130. 1974.
  •  30
    We Don’t Owe Them a Thing!
    The Monist 86 (3): 419-433. 2003.
    The discovery that people far away are in bad shape seems to generate a sense of guilt on the part of many articulate people in our part of the world, even though they are no worse off now that we’ve heard about them than they had been before. I will take it as given that we are certainly responsible for evils we inflict on others, no matter where, and that we owe those people compensation. Not all similarly agree that it is not in general our duty to make other people better off, and therefore …Read more
  • David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement (review)
    Philosophy in Review 7 269-272. 1987.
  •  10
    Silverstein on egoism and universalizability
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (3). 1969.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  • J.R. Lucas, On Justice (review)
    Philosophy in Review 2 27-29. 1982.
  •  257
    Utilitarianism and formalism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 43 (1): 58-72. 1965.
    No abstract
  •  305
    Utilitarianism and new generations
    Mind 76 (301): 62-72. 1967.
  •  8
    Pacifism: A Comment on Beehler's Note
    Dialogue 11 (4): 588-591. 1972.
  •  51
    Reply to Dworkin
    Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (1): 41. 1983.
    My main complaint about Dworkin's papers on equality was that he had not said much by way of arguing for it. His intriguing response to this request provides a good start, and I shall confine this brief, further comment to what he says on that basic subject. Space considerations, alas, require me to ignore the other parts of his discussion. Dworkin distinguishes what he calls the “abstract egalitarian thesis” from his particular version of equalitarianism, equality of resources. His strategy is …Read more
  •  137
    Is pacifism consistent?
    Ethics 78 (2): 148-150. 1968.
  •  831
    The nature and value of rights
    Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (4): 243-260. 1970.
  •  28
    On Defense by Nuclear Deterrence
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (sup1): 195-211. 1986.
    (1986). On Defense by Nuclear Deterrence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 16, Supplementary Volume 12: Nuclear Weapons, Deterrence and Disarmament, pp. 195-211
  •  23
    Charles Taylor., The Ethics of Authenticity (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 26 (2): 147-148. 1994.
  •  5
    Rights and Utilitarianism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 5 (n/a): 137-160. 1979.
    Few questions about utilitarianism have been more vexed than that of its relation to rights. It is commonplace to hold that there are nonutilitarian rights, rights not founded on considerations of utility. And it is even thought that the very notion of rights is inherently incapable of being significantly employed within the utilitarian framework. In the present paper, I wish to consider both of these matters. I propose to give reasons—mostly not really new—for rejecting the stronger, conceptual…Read more