Peter Goldie

Manchester
  • Manchester
    Department Of Philosophy
    Samuel Hall Chair In Philosophy
University of Oxford
Faculty of Philosophy
DPhil, 1997
  •  70
    XII. Narrative and Perspective; Values and Appropriate Emotions
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 52 201-220. 2003.
    To the realists.—You sober people who feel well armed against passion and fantasies and would like to turn your emptiness into a matter of pride and ornament: you call yourselves realists and hint that the world really is the way it appears to you. As if reality stood unveiled before you only, and you yourselves were perhaps the best part of it … But in your unveiled state are not even you still very passionate and dark creatures compared to fish, and still far too similar to an artist in love? …Read more
  •  94
    The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    This Handbook presents thirty-one state-of-the-art contributions from the most notable writers on philosophy of emotion today. Anyone working on the nature of emotion, its history, or its relation to reason, self, value, or art, whether at the level of research or advanced study, will find the book an unrivalled resource and a fascinating read
  •  301
    Grief: A narrative account
    Ratio 24 (2): 119-137. 2011.
    Grief is not a kind of feeling, or a kind of judgement, or a kind of perception, or any kind of mental state or event the identity of which can be adequately captured at a moment in time. Instead, grief is a kind of process; more specifically, it is a complex pattern of activity and passivity, inner and outer, which unfolds over time, and the unfolding pattern over time is explanatorily prior to what is the case at any particular time. The pattern of a particular grieving is best understood and …Read more
  •  214
    There is a view of the emotions (I might tendentiously call it ‘cognitivism’) that has at present a certain currency. This view is of the emotions as playing an essential role in our gaining evaluative knowledge of the world. When we are angry at an insult, or afraid of the burglar, our emotions involve evaluative perceptions and thoughts, which are directed towards the way something is in the world that impinges on our well-being, or on the well-being of those that matter to us. Without emotion…Read more
  •  152
    Towards a virtue theory of art
    British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (4): 372-387. 2007.
    In this paper I sketch a virtue theory of art, analogous to a virtue theory of ethics along Aristotelian lines. What this involves is looking beyond a parochial conception of art understood as work of art, as product, to include intentions, motives, skills, traits, and feelings, all of which can be expressed in artistic activity. The clusters of traits that go to make up the particular virtues of art production and of art appreciation are indeed virtues in part because, when they are expressed i…Read more
  •  2
    Conceptual art and knowledge
    In Peter Goldie & Elisabeth Schellekens (eds.), Philosophy and Conceptual Art, Oxford University Press. pp. 157. 2007.
  •  107
    On personality
    Routledge. 2004.
    The pervasiveness of personality -- Good and bad people : a question of character -- The fragility of character -- Character, responsibility and circumspection -- personality, narrative and living a life.
  •  56
    Life, Fiction, and Narrative
    In Noel Carroll & John Gibson (eds.), Narrative, Emotion, and Insight, Penn State University. pp. 8. 2011.
  • Understanding Emotions. Mind and Morals
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (4): 777-778. 2004.
  •  115
    Intellectual Emotions and Religious Emotions
    Faith and Philosophy 28 (1): 93-101. 2011.
    What is the best model of emotion if we are to reach a good understanding of the role of emotion in religious life? I begin by setting out a simple model of emotion, based on a paradigm emotional experience of fear of an immediate threat in one’s environment. I argue that the simple model neglects many of the complexities of our emotional lives, including in particular the complexities that one finds with the intellectual emotions. I then discuss how our dispositions to have these kinds of emoti…Read more
  •  83
    Emotion, reason and virtue
    In Dylan Evans & Pierre Cruse (eds.), Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality, Oxford University Press. pp. 249--267. 2004.
  •  294
    Emotion
    Philosophy Compass 2 (6). 2007.
    After many years of neglect, philosophers are increasingly turning their attention to the emotions, and recently we have seen a number of different accounts of emotion. In this article, we will first consider what facts an account of emotion needs to accommodate if it is going to be acceptable. Having done that, we will then consider some of the leading accounts and see how they fare in accommodating the facts. Two things in particular will emerge. First, an adequate account of emotion cannot be…Read more
  •  130
    Getting Feelings into Emotional Experiences in the Right Way
    Emotion Review 1 (3): 232-239. 2009.
    I argue that emotional feelings are not just bodily feelings, but also feelings directed towards things in the world beyond the bounds of the body, and that these feelings (feelings towards) are bound up with the way we take in the world in emotional experience
  •  500
    Emotions, feelings and intentionality
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1 (3): 235-254. 2002.
    Emotions, I will argue, involve two kinds of feeling: bodily feeling and feeling towards. Both are intentional, in the sense of being directed towards an object. Bodily feelings are directed towards the condition of one's body, although they can reveal truths about the world beyond the bounds of one's body – that, for example, there is something dangerous nearby. Feelings towards are directed towards the object of the emotion – a thing or a person, a state of affairs, an action or an event; such…Read more
  •  33
    Compassion: Α Natural, Moral Emotion
    In Verena Mayer & Sabine A. Döring (eds.), Die Moralität der Gefühle, De Gruyter. pp. 199-212. 2002.
  •  23
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 642-648. 1998.
  •  49
    Loss of Affect in Intellectual Activity
    Emotion Review 4 (2): 122-126. 2012.
    In this article I will consider how loss of affect in our intellectual lives, through depression for example, can be as debilitating as loss of affect elsewhere in our lives. This will involve showing that there are such things as intellectual emotions, that their role in intellectual activity is not merely as an aid to the intellect, and that loss of affect changes not only one’s motivations, but also one’s overall evaluative take on the world
  •  123
    Virtues of Art
    Philosophy Compass 5 (10): 830-839. 2010.
    The idea that there is an important place in philosophical aesthetics for virtues of art is not new, but it is now undergoing a serious re‐examination. Why might this be? What are the principles behind virtue aesthetics? Are there any good arguments for the theory? (I will take virtue aesthetics to be the theory that there is a central place for virtues of art.) What problems does virtue aesthetics face? And what might the implications be of virtue aesthetics both in philosophy and in related di…Read more
  •  212
    Virtues of art and human well-being
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 82 (1): 179-195. 2008.
    What is the point of art, and why does it matter to us human beings? The answer that I will give in this paper, following on from an earlier paper on the same subject, is that art matters because our being actively engaged with art, either in its production or in its appreciation, is part of what it is to live well. The focus in the paper will be on the dispositions—the virtues of art production and of art appreciation—that are necessary for this kind of active engagement with art. To begin with…Read more