•  17
    Individualism and Supervenience
    with Jerry Fodor
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 (1): 235-283. 1986.
  • Consciousness and explanation
    In Lawrence Weiskrantz & Martin Davies (eds.), Frontiers of consciousness, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  •  10
    Sitting in the philosopher’s armchair, I am not engaged in any detailed empirical investigation of the world. But, as I pursue philosophy’s distinctive armchair methodology, I sometimes come upon arguments that appear to disclose requirements for thought. According to some of these arguments, being a thinking person requires having the right kind of history, or having the right kind of cognitive architecture. According to other arguments, being able to think about particular topics requires bein…Read more
  •  23
    As an undergraduate from 1964 to 1967, Gareth Evans, a British philosopher of language and mind, studied for the PPE degree (philosophy, politics and economics) at University College, Oxford, where his philosophy tutor was Peter Strawson. He was then a Senior Scholar at Christ Church, Oxford (1967–68) and a Kennedy Scholar visiting Harvard and Berkeley (1968–69). In 1968, less than a year after completing his degree, Evans was elected to a Fellowship at University College. He took up the positio…Read more
  •  63
    Spatial limits on the nonvisual self-touch illusion and the visual rubber hand illusion: Subjective experience of the illusion and proprioceptive drift
    with Anne M. Aimola Davies and Rebekah C. White
    Consciousness and Cognition 22 (2): 613-636. 2013.
    The nonvisual self-touch rubber hand paradigm elicits the compelling illusion that one is touching one’s own hand even though the two hands are not in contact. In four experiments, we investigated spatial limits of distance and alignment on the nonvisual self-touch illusion and the well-known visual rubber hand illusion. Common procedures and common assessment methods were used. Subjective experience of the illusion was assessed by agreement ratings for statements on a questionnaire and time of …Read more
  •  55
    Ethics briefing
    with Sophie Brannan, Eleanor Chrispin, Veronica English, Rebecca Mussell, and Julian C. Sheather
    Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (6): 413-414. 2013.
    Ever so often in the UK, there is a flurry of activity around the information requirements of donor-conceived individuals. In April 2013, it was the launch of a report from the Nuffield Council on Bioethics that brought the issue back to public consciousness.1Since 1991, information about treatment with donor gametes or embryos has been collected by the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority . Since then, over 35 000 donor-conceived individuals have been born through treatment in licensed …Read more
  •  74
    Mental simulation is the simulation, replication or re-enactment, usually in imagination, of the thinking, decision-making, emotional responses, or other aspects of the mental life of another person. According to simulation theory, mental simulation in imagination plays a key role in our everyday psychological understanding of other people. The same mental resources that are used in our own thinking, decision-making or emotional responses are redeployed in imagination to provide an understanding…Read more
  •  35
    Frontiers of consciousness (edited book)
    with Lawrence Weiskrantz
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    In recent years consciousness has become a significant area of study in the cognitive sciences. The Frontiers of Consciousness is a major interdisciplinary exploration of consciousness. The book stems from the Chichele lectures held at All Souls College in Oxford, and features contributions from a 'who's who' of authorities from both philosophy and psychology. The result is a truly interdisciplinary volume, which tackles some of the biggest and most impenetrable problems in consciousness. The bo…Read more
  •  23
    from the fact that the subject reacts faster to those words than to words that were not on the list. The subject
  • Poggio Bracciolini
    In Jill Kraye (ed.), Cambridge translations of Renaissance philosophical texts, Cambridge University Press. pp. 135. 1997.
  • The Boolos Panel
    with W. V. Quine, George Boolos, Paul Horwich, and Rudolf Fara
    Philosophy International. 1994.
  •  349
    Connectionism, modularity, and tacit knowledge
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (December): 541-55. 1989.
    In this paper, I define tacit knowledge as a kind of causal-explanatory structure, mirroring the derivational structure in the theory that is tacitly known. On this definition, tacit knowledge does not have to be explicitly represented. I then take the notion of a modular theory, and project the idea of modularity to several different levels of description: in particular, to the processing level and the neurophysiological level. The fundamental description of a connectionist network lies at a le…Read more
  •  39
    Meaning and structure
    Philosophia 13 (1-2): 13-33. 1983.
  •  33
    Aunty's own argument for the language of thought
    In Jes Ezquerro (ed.), Cognition, Semantics and Philosophy, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 235--271. 1992.
  •  15
    Individualism and Perceptual Content
    Mind 100 (4): 461-484. 1991.
  •  22
    He then argues that (1), (2) and (3) constitute an inconsistent triad as follows (1991, p. 15): Suppose (1) that Oscar knows a priori that he is thinking that water is wet. Then by (2), Oscar can simply deduce E, using premisses that are knowable a priori, including the premiss that he is thinking that water is wet. Since Oscar can deduce E from premisses that are knowable a priori, Oscar can know E itself a priori. But this contradicts (3), the assumption that E cannot be known a priori. Hence …Read more
  •  110
    Inference and explanation in cognitive neuropsychology
    with Max Coltheart
    Cortex 39 (1): 188-191. 2003.
    The question posed by Dunn and Kirsner (D&K) is an instance of a more general one: What can we infer from data? One answer, if we are talking about logically valid deductive inference, is that we cannot infer theories from data. A theory is supposed to explain the data and so cannot be a mere summary of the data to be explained. The truth of an explanatory theory goes beyond the data and so is never logically guaranteed by the data. This is not just a point about cognitive neuropsychology, or ev…Read more
  •  84
    Function in perception
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4): 409-426. 1983.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  192
    In his paper ‘Scmantic Theory and Tacit Knowlcdgc’, Gareth Evans uscs a familiar kind of cxamplc in ordcr to render vivid his account of tacit knowledge. We arc to consider a finite language, with just one hundrcd scntcnccs. Each scntcncc is made up of a subjcct (a name) and a prcdicatc. The names are ‘a’, ‘b’, . . ., T. The prcdicatcs arc ‘F’, ‘G’, . . ., ‘O’. Thc scntcnccs have meanings which dcpcnd in a systematic way upon their construction. Thus, all scntcnccs containing ‘a’ mean something …Read more
  •  33
    Ethics briefings
    with Sophie Brannan, Eleanor Chrispin, Veronica English, and Rebecca Mussell
    Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (11): 701-702. 2012.
  •  20
    Relevance and mutual knowledge
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4): 716. 1987.
  •  152
    Cognitive neuropsychology and the philosophy of mind
    with Tony Stone
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (4): 589-622. 1993.
  •  120
    Externalism, architecturalism, and epistemic warrant
    In C. Macdonald, Barry C. Smith & C. J. G. Wright (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds: Essays in Self-Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 321-363. 1998.
    This paper addresses a problem about epistemic warrant. The problem is posed by philosophical arguments for externalism about the contents of thoughts, and similarly by philosophical arguments for architecturalism about thinking, when these arguments are put together with a thesis of first person authority. In each case, first personal knowledge about our thoughts plus the kind of knowledge that is provided by a philosophical argument seem, together, to open an unacceptably ‘non-empirical’ route…Read more
  •  1
    Philosophisch-medizinische Aufsätze
    with Marcus Herz
    . 1997.
  •  2
    Consciousness: A Mind and Language Reader (edited book)
    with G. Humphreys
    Blackwell. 1993.
  •  264
    Starting from Dennett's distinction between personal and sub-personal levels of description, I consider the relationships amongst three levels: the personal level, the level of information-processing mechanisms, and the level of neurobiology. I defend a conception of the relationship between the personal level and the sub-personal level of information-processing mechanisms as interaction without reduction . Even given a nonreductionist conception of persons, philosophical theorizing sometimes su…Read more
  •  172
    Anosognosia and the Two‐factor Theory of Delusions
    with Anne Aimola Davies and Max Coltheart
    Mind and Language 20 (2): 209-236. 2005.
    Anosognosia is literally ‘unawareness of or failure to acknowledge one’s hemi- plegia or other disability’ (OED). Etymology would suggest the meaning ‘lack of knowledge of disease’ so that anosognosia would include any denial of impairment, such as denial of blindness (Anton’s syndrome). But Babinski, who introduced the term in 1914, applied it only to patients with hemiplegia who fail to acknowledge their paralysis. Most commonly, this is failure to acknowledge paralysis of the left side of the…Read more