•  42
    Between ontological hubris and epistemic humility: Collingwood, Kant and the role of transcendental arguments
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (2): 336-357. 2019.
    This paper explores and defends a form of transcendental argument that is neither bold in its attempt to answer the sceptic, as ambitious transcendental strategies, nor epistemically humble, as modest transcendental strategies. While ambitious transcendental strategies seek to meet the sceptical challenge, and modest transcendental strategies accept the validity of the challenge but retreat to a position of epistemic humility, this form of transcendental argument denies the assumption that under…Read more
  •  317
    The touch of King Midas: Collingwood on why actions are not events
    Philosophical Explorations 21 (1): 160-169. 2018.
    It is the ambition of natural science to provide complete explanations of reality. Collingwood argues that science can only explain events, not actions. The latter is the distinctive subject matter of history and can be described as actions only if they are explained historically. This paper explains Collingwood’s claim that the distinctive subject matter of history is actions and why the attempt to capture this subject matter through the method of science inevitably ends in failure because scie…Read more
  •  17
    Defending Humanistic Reasoning
    Philosophy Now 123 31-33. 2017.
  • Collingwood and the Metaphysics of Experience
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 66 (2): 365-368. 2004.
  • Hermeneutics and Truth (review)
    Radical Philosophy 76. 1996.
  •  70
    This paper seeks to explain why mainstream analytic philosophy lost interest in the philosophy of history. It suggests that the reasons why the philosophy of history no longer commands the attention of mainstream analytical philosophy may be explained by the success of an ontological backlash against the linguistic turn and a view of philosophy as a form of conceptual analysis. In brief I argue that in the 1950s and 1960s the philosophy of history attracted the interest of mainstream analytical …Read more
  •  1
    On Collingwood's Conceptions of History'
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 7 45-69. 2000.
  •  27
    This paper explores an alternative to the metaphysical challenge to physicalism posed by Jackson and Kripke and to the epistemological one exemplified by the positions of Nagel, Levine and Mcginn. On this alternative the mind-body gap is neither ontological nor epistemological, but semantic. I claim that it is because the gap is semantic that the mind body-problem is a quintessentially philosophical problem that is not likely to wither away as our natural scientific knowledge advances
  •  39
    Collingwood on philosophical knowledge and the enduring nature of philosophical problems
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (1). 2004.
    No abstract
  •  127
    The gap is semantic, not epistemological
    Ratio 20 (2): 168-178. 2007.
    This paper explores an alternative to the metaphysical challenge to physicalism posed by Jackson and Kripke and to the epistemological one exemplified by the positions of Nagel, Levine and McGinn. On this alternative the mind‐body gap is neither ontological nor epistemological, but semantic. I claim that it is because the gap is semantic that the mind‐body problem is a quintessentially philosophical problem that is not likely to wither away as our natural scientific knowledge advances.1.
  •  42
    The Philosopher and the Grapes: On Descriptive Metaphysics and Why It Is Not ‘Sour Metaphysics’
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (4): 586-599. 2013.
    There is a widespread view according to which descriptive metaphysics is not ‘real’ metaphysics. This paper argues that first-order philosophical disagreements cannot be settled without re-opening the debate about the nature of philosophical enquiry and that failure to scrutinize and justify one’s own metaphilosophical stance leads to arguments which are circular or question begging.
  •  38
    On Collingwood's Rehabilitation of the Ontological Argument
    Idealistic Studies 30 (3): 173-188. 2000.
    The paper is divided in two parts. In the first I consider the nature of Ryle's attack on Collingwood's appropriation of the ontological argument and Collingwood's defence in the unpublished correspondence. In the second, I go beyond the confines of the Ryle-Collingwood exchange in the mid 'thirties to say something much more general about the nature of Collingwood's metaphysics as well as to advance an explanation of the compatibility of Collingwood's combined defence of descriptive metaphysics…Read more
  •  95
    Collingwood on re-enactment and the identity of thought
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (1): 87-101. 2000.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 38.1 (2000) 87-101 [Access article in PDF] Collingwood on Re-Enactment and The Identity of Thought Giuseppina D'oro University of Keele Collingwood's The Idea of History is often discussed in the context of the issue of the reducibility/non-reducibility of explanations in the social sciences to explanations in the natural sciences. In the 1950s and 60s, following the publication of Hempel's influe…Read more
  •  35
    The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2017.
    The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology offers clear and comprehensive coverage of the main methodological debates and approaches within philosophy. The chapters in this volume approach the question of how to do philosophy from a wide range of perspectives, including conceptual analysis, critical theory, deconstruction, experimental philosophy, hermeneutics, Kantianism, methodological naturalism, phenomenology, and pragmatism. They explore general conceptions of philosophy, centred …Read more
  •  37
    Reclaiming the ancestors of simulation theory (review)
    History and Theory 48 (1): 129-139. 2009.
  • De la distinction entre action et événement
    Recherches Sur la Philosophie Et le Langage 30 169-186. 2014.
  •  76
    Collingwood and Ryle on the concept of mind
    Philosophical Explorations 6 (1). 2003.
    This paper argues that Collingwood's philosophy of mind offers an interesting and compelling account of the nature of the mind and of the irreducibility of the mental, an account whose viability and relevance to contemporary debates ought to be given serious consideration. I suggest that the reason why Collingwood's contribution to the philosophy of mind has been neglected is due to the fact that his philosophy of mind is widely, even if mistakenly, regarded as the target of Ryle's attacks on th…Read more
  •  53
    Unlikely Bedfellows? Collingwood, Carnap and the Internal/External Distinction
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (4): 802-817. 2015.
    Idealism is often associated with the kind of metaphysical system building which was successfully disposed of by logical positivism. As Hume's fork was intended to deliver a serious blow to Leibnizian metaphysics so logical positivism invoked the verificationist principle against the reawakening of metaphysics, in the tradition of German and British idealism. In the light of this one might reasonably wonder what Carnap's pragmatism could possibly have in common with Collingwood's idealism. After…Read more
  •  126
    Reasons and Causes: The Philosophical Battle and The Meta-philosophical War
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2). 2012.
    ?Are the reasons for acting also the causes of action?? When this question was asked in the early 1960s it received by and large a negative reply: ?No, reasons are not causes?. Yet, when the same question ?Are the reasons for acting the causes of action?? is posed some twenty years later, the predominant answer is ?Yes, reasons are causes?. How could one and the same question receive such diverging answers in the space of only a couple of decades? This paper argues that the shift from an anti-ca…Read more
  •  80
    Collingwood, psychologism and internalism
    European Journal of Philosophy 12 (2). 2004.
    The paper defends Collingwood's account of rational explanation against two objections. The first is that he psychologizes the concept of practical reason. The second is that he fails to distinguish mere rationalizations from rationalizations that have causal power. I argue that Collingwood endorses a form of nonpsychologizing internalism which rests on the view that the appropriate explanans for actions are neither empirical facts (as externalists claim), nor psychological facts (as some intern…Read more
  •  299
    Two dogmas of contemporary philosophy of action
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 1 (1): 10-24. 2007.
    Davidson's seminal essay "Actions, Reasons and Causes" brought about a paradigm shift in the theory of action. Before Davidson the consensus was that the fundamental task of a theory of action was to elucidate the concept of action and event explanation. The debate concerning the nature of action explanation thus took place primarily in the philosophy of history and social science and was focussed on purely methodological issues. After Davidson it has been assumed that the fundamental challenge …Read more
  •  5
    Introduction
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 22 (1): 1-14. 2016.