•  37
    The two main insights of the account that are at the heart of the notion of knowledge are that the belief that p amounts to high token indicativity of the fact that p, and that knowledge endows high level of immunity from error. In this outline we shall deal with perceptual knowledge and perception-based memory. For these modes of knowledge, another condition is required, beyond that of high token indicativity, which secures the appropriate discriminability condition for knowledge. These conditi…Read more
  • The omnipotence puzzle
    Logique Et Analyse 25 (97): 75. 1982.
  •  264
    Abstract In this paper I consider an easier-to-read and improved to a certain extent version of the causal chance-based analysis of counterfactuals that I proposed and argued for in my A Theory of Counterfactuals. Sections 2, 3 and 4 form Part I: In it, I survey the analysis of the core counterfactuals (in which, very roughly, the antecedent is compatible with history prior to it). In section 2 I go through the three main aspects of this analysis, which are the following. First, it is a caus…Read more
  •  80
    In this paper I explore the ambiguity that arises between two readings of the counterfactual construction, then–d and thel–p, analyzed in my bookA Theory of Counterfactuals. I then extend the analysis I offered there to counterfactuals with true antecedents, and offer a more precise formulation of the conception of temporal divergence points used in thel–p interpretation. Finally, I discuss some ramifications of these issues for counterfactual analyses of knowledge.
  •  99
    Kripke's Belief Puzzle
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1): 287-325. 1986.
    This article offers a resolution of Kripke’s well-known belief puzzle
  •  130
    The Counterfactual Analysis of Cause
    Synthese 127 (3): 389-427. 2001.
    David Lewis’s counterfactual analysis of cause consisted of the counterfactual conditional closed under transitivity.2 Namely, a sufficient condition for A’s being a cause of C is that ∼A > ∼C be true; and a necessary as well as sufficient condition is that there be a series of true counterfactuals ∼A > ∼E1, ∼E1 > ∼E2, . . . , ∼En >∼C (n > 0).
  •  278
    In the past couple of decades, there were a few major attempts to establish the thesis of pragmatic infringement – that a significant pragmatic ingredient figures significantly in the truth-conditions for knowledge-ascriptions. As candidates, epistemic contextualism and Relativism flaunted conversational standards, and Stanley's SSI promoted stakes. These conceptions were propelled first and foremost by obviously pragmatic examples of knowledge ascriptions that seem to require a pragmatic compon…Read more
  •  2
  •  91
    A probabilistic theory of knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1). 2006.
    In this paper I provide a probabilistic account of factual knowledge,[1] based on the notion of chance.[2] This account has some affinity with my chance account of token causation,[3] but it neither relies on it nor presupposes it. Here I concentrate on the core cases of perceptual knowledge and of knowledge by memory (based on perception). The analysis of knowledge presented below is externalist; but pursuing such an analysis need not detract from the significance of attempts to flesh out justi…Read more
  • The Paradox Of Surprise Examination
    Logique Et Analyse 21 (82): 337-344. 1978.
  •  273
    I argue that 'know' is only partly, though considerably, gradable. Its being only partly gradable is explained by its multi-parametrical character. That is, its truth-conditions involve different parameters, which are scalar in character, each of which is fully gradable. Robustness of knowledge may be higher or lower along different dimensions and different modes. This has little to do with whether 'know' is context-dependent, but it undermines Stanley's argument that the non-gradability of 'kno…Read more
  •  67
    Quine and Modalities De Re
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (6): 295-328. 1982.
  •  30
    Kripke’s Belief Puzzle
    Philosophy Research Archives 9 369-412. 1983.
    This article offers a resolution of Kripke’s well-known belief puzzle.
  •  62
    Beliefs and believing
    Theoria 52 (3): 129-45. 1986.
  •  31
    On Putnam's counterexample toa theory of counterfactuals
    Philosophical Papers 16 (3): 235-239. 1987.
    No abstract
  •  62
    The Hesperus-Phosphorus case
    Theoria 50 (1): 1-35. 1984.