Edinburgh, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  20
    What Am I? Virtual Machines and the Mind/body Problem
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2): 237-309. 2008.
    When your word processor or email program is running on your computer, this creates a “virtual machine” that manipulates windows, files, text, etc. What is this virtual machine, and what are the virtual objects it manipulates? Many standard arguments in the philosophy of mind have exact analogues for virtual machines and virtual objects, but we do not want to draw the wild metaphysical conclusions that have sometimes tempted philosophers in the philosophy of mind. A computer file is not made of …Read more
  •  24
    Vision, Knowledge, and the Mystery Link
    with Iris Oved
    Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1): 309-351. 2005.
  •  183
    What am I? Virtual machines and the mind/body problem
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2). 2008.
    When your word processor or email program is running on your computer, this creates a "virtual machine” that manipulates windows, files, text, etc. What is this virtual machine, and what are the virtual objects it manipulates? Many standard arguments in the philosophy of mind have exact analogues for virtual machines and virtual objects, but we do not want to draw the wild metaphysical conclusions that have sometimes tempted philosophers in the philosophy of mind. A computer file is not made of …Read more
  •  6
    VI. Formal Semantics
    In The foundations of philosophical semantics, Princeton University Press. pp. 172-229. 1984.
  •  190
    Vision, knowledge, and the mystery link
    with Iris Oved
    Noûs 39 (1): 309-351. 2005.
    Imagine yourself sitting on your front porch, sipping your morning coffee and admiring the scene before you. You see trees, houses, people, automobiles; you see a cat running across the road, and a bee buzzing among the flowers. You see that the flowers are yellow, and blowing in the wind. You see that the people are moving about, many of them on bicycles. You see that the houses are painted different colors, mostly earth tones, and most are one-story but a few are two-story. It is a beautiful m…Read more
  • V. Causation
    In The foundations of philosophical semantics, Princeton University Press. pp. 148-171. 1984.
  •  97
    Understanding the language of thought
    Philosophical Studies 58 (1-2): 95-120. 1990.
    The author poses a question: when a person has a thought, what is it that determines what thought he is having? and, equivalently, what is it that determines what thought he is having. looking for an answer he sketches some general aspects of the problems involved in answering these questions, like the mind/body problem, for example. his conclusion is that the posed questions should be set against the background assumption that thoughts are just internal physical occurrences, and that thoughts a…Read more
  •  269
    The theory of nomic probability
    Synthese 90 (2). 1992.
    This article sketches a theory of objective probability focusing on nomic probability, which is supposed to be the kind of probability figuring in statistical laws of nature. The theory is based upon a strengthened probability calculus and some epistemological principles that formulate a precise version of the statistical syllogism. It is shown that from this rather minimal basis it is possible to derive theorems comprising (1) a theory of direct inference, and (2) a theory of induction. The the…Read more
  •  11
    ``The Paradox of the Preface"
    Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 246-258. 1986.
    In a number of recent papers I have been developing the theory of “nomic probability,“ which is supposed to be the kind of probability involved in statistical laws of nature. One of the main principles of this theory is an acceptance rule explicitly designed to handle the lottery paradox. This paper shows that the rule can also handle the paradox of the preface. The solution proceeds in part by pointing out a surprising connection between the paradox of the preface and the gambler's fallacy.
  •  24
    The Phylogeny of Rationality
    Cognitive Science 17 (4): 563-588. 1993.
    A rational agent has beliefs reflecting the state of its environment, and likes or dislikes Its situation. When it finds the world not entirely to Its liking, it tries to change that. We can, accordingly, evaluate a system of cognition in terms of its probable success in bringing about situations that are to the agent's liking. In doing this we are viewing practical reasoning from “the design stance.” It is argued that a considerable amount of the structure of rationality can be elicited as prov…Read more
  •  124
    The paradox of the preface
    Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 246-258. 1986.
    In a number of recent papers I have been developing the theory of "nomic probability," which is supposed to be the kind of probability involved in statistical laws of nature. One of the main principles of this theory is an acceptance rule explicitly designed to handle the lottery paradox. This paper shows that the rule can also handle the paradox of the preface. The solution proceeds in part by pointing out a surprising connection between the paradox of the preface and the gambler's fallacy
  •  47
    The logic of projectibility
    Philosophy of Science 39 (3): 302-314. 1972.
    Projectible conditions are (roughly) those whose universal generalizations are con firmed by their positive instances. This paper proposes certain modifications to the above definition in order to capture the pre-analytic notion it is supposed to explicate. Then we investigate what logical operations, when performed on projectible conditionals, yield new projectible conditionals. A number of surprising theorems are proven, and these theorems indicate that few conditionals having complex antecede…Read more
  •  74
    The objective of this book is to produce a theory of rational decision making for realistically resource-bounded agents. My interest is not in “What should I do if I were an ideal agent?”, but rather, “What should I do given that I am who I am, with all my actual cognitive limitations?” The book has three parts. Part One addresses the question of where the values come from that agents use in rational decision making. The most comon view among philosophers is that they are based on preferences, b…Read more
  •  27
    The building of Oscar
    Philosophical Perspectives 2 315-344. 1988.
  •  151
    Self-defeating arguments
    Minds and Machines 1 (4): 367-392. 1991.
    An argument is self-defeating when it contains defeaters for some of its own defeasible lines. It is shown that the obvious rules for defeat among arguments do not handle self-defeating arguments correctly. It turns out that they constitute a pervasive phenomenon that threatens to cripple defeasible reasoning, leading to almost all defeasible reasoning being defeated by unexpected interactions with self-defeating arguments. This leads to some important changes in the general theory of defeasible…Read more
  •  11
    Reply to Shope
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (2): 411-413. 1992.
  •  38
    Rationality, function, and content
    Philosophical Studies 65 (1-2): 129-151. 1992.
    To summarize, in order for rational agents to be able to engage in the sophisticated kinds of reasoning exemplified by human beings, they must be able to introspect much of their cognition. The problem of other minds and the problem of knowing the mental states of others will arise automatically for any rational agent that is able to introspect its own cognition. The most that a rational agent can reasonably believe about other rational agents is that they have rational architectures similar to …Read more
  •  125
    Reasoning defeasibly about probabilities
    Synthese 181 (2): 317-352. 2011.
    In concrete applications of probability, statistical investigation gives us knowledge of some probabilities, but we generally want to know many others that are not directly revealed by our data. For instance, we may know prob(P/Q) (the probability of P given Q) and prob(P/R), but what we really want is prob(P/Q& R), and we may not have the data required to assess that directly. The probability calculus is of no help here. Given prob(P/Q) and prob(P/R), it is consistent with the probability calcu…Read more
  •  33
    Rational Choice and Action Omnipotence
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 1. 2002.
    A theory of rational choice is a theory of how an agent should, rationally, go about deciding what actions to perform at any given time. For example, I may want to decide whether to go to a movie this evening or stay home and read a book. The actions between which we want to choose are perfectly ordinary actions, and the presumption is that to make such a decision we should attend to the likely consequences of our decision. It is assumed that these decisions must be made in the face of uncertain…Read more
  •  110
    Reliability and Justified Belief
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (1). 1984.
    Reliabilist theories propose to analyse epistemic justification in terms of reliability. This paper argues that if we pay attention to the details of probability theory we find that there is no concept of reliability that can possibly play the role required by reliabilist theories. A distinction is drawn between the general reliability of a process and the single case reliability of an individual belief, And it is argued that neither notion can serve the reliabilist adequately
  •  2
    References
    In The foundations of philosophical semantics, Princeton University Press. pp. 230-236. 1984.
  •  30
    Practical reasoning in Oscar
    Philosophical Perspectives 9 15-48. 1995.
  •  2
    Preface
    In The foundations of philosophical semantics, Princeton University Press. 1984.
  •  46
    Oscar
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 6 (1): 89-113. 1996.
    In its present incarnation, OSCAR is a fully implemented programmable architecture for a rational agent. If we just focus upon the epistemic reasoning in OSCAR, we have a powerful general-purpose defeasible reasoner. The purpose of this paper is to describe that reasoner. OSCAR's defeasible reasoner is based upon seven fundamental ideas. These are (1) an argument-based account of defeasible reasoning, (2) an analysis of defeat-status given a set of interrelated arguments, (3) a general adequacy …Read more
  •  64
    Oscar
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 6 (1): 89-113. 1996.
    OSCAR is a fully implemented architecture for a cognitive agent, based largely on the author’s work in philosophy concerning epistemology and practical cognition. The seminal idea is that a generally intelligent agent must be able to function in an environment in which it is ignorant of most matters of fact. The architecture incorporates a general-purpose defeasible reasoner, built on top of an efficient natural deduction reasoner for first-order logic. It is based upon a detailed theory about h…Read more
  •  129
    Nomic probability
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1): 177-204. 1984.