Temple University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
Iowa City, Iowa, United States of America
  •  131
    Do mystics see God?
    In Michael L. Peterson & Raymond J. VanArragon (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion, Blackwell. pp. 145--148. 2004.
  •  132
    Uniqueness and historical laws
    Philosophy of Science 47 (2): 260-276. 1980.
    This paper presents an argument for the claim that historical events are unique in a nontrivial sense which entails the inapplicability of the Hempelian D-N model to historical explanations. Some previous criticisms of Hempel are shown to be general criticisms of the D-N model which can be outflanked in cases where a reduction to fundamental laws is available. I then survey grounds for denying that explanations by reasons can be effectively reduced to causal explanations, and for rejecting metho…Read more
  •  79
    Can science explain mysticism?
    Religious Studies 35 (2): 213-227. 1999.
    Jerome Gellman has recently disputed my claim that a naturalistic explanation for mystical experiences is available, a better explanation than any current attempt to show that God is sometimes perceived in those experiences. Gellman argues (i) that some mystics do not 'fit' the sociological explanation of I. M. Lewis; (ii) that the sociological analysis of tribal mysticism cannot properly be extended to theistic experiences; and (iii) that mystical experiences merit prima facie credence, so the …Read more
  •  48
    Several writers have argued for the implausibility of there being naturalistic explanations of mystical experience. These writers recognize that the evidential significance of mystical experiences for theism depends upon whether explanations that exclude supernatural agency can be discounted; but they seem unaware of some of the best scientific work done in this area. Part I of the present paper introduces the theory of I. M. Lewis, an anthropologist, and tests it against the case of St Teresa. …Read more
  •  141
    A Defense of the Given
    Lanham: Rowman &Amp; Littlefield. 1996.
    The Doctrine of the Given The Myth of the Given A Methodological Problem To a convinced foundationalist, the project of establishing the existence of the ...
  •  87
    Reformed Epistemology and Biblical Hermeneutics
    Philo 4 (2): 169-184. 2001.
    Literal-minded Christians are enjoying resurgent respectability in intellectual circles. Darwin isn’t the only target: also under attack is the application of modern historiography to Scripture According to Reformed epistemologists, ordinary Christians can directly know that, e.g., Jesus rose from the dead, and evidential concerns can be dismissed. This reversion to a sixteenth century hermeneutic deserves response.
  •  72
    Natural kinds and freaks of nature
    Philosophy of Science 49 (1): 67-90. 1982.
    Essentialism--understood as the doctrine that there are natural kinds--can be sustained with respect to the most fundamental physical entities of the world, as I elsewhere argue. In this paper I take up the question of the existence of natural kinds among complex structures built out of these elementary ones. I consider a number of objections to essentialism, in particular Locke's puzzle about the existence of borderline cases. A number of recent attempts to justify biological taxonomy are criti…Read more
  •  76
    Despair, Optimism, and Rebellion
    Internet Infidels, Modern Library. 2007.
    I will make all my goodness pass before you, and will proclaim before you my name 'the LORD'; and I will be gracious to whom I will be gracious, and will show mercy on whom I will show mercy. But ... you cannot see my face; for man shall not see me and live. Exodus 33:19-20, RSV..
  •  105
    Is a Science of the Supernatural Possible?
    In Massimo Pigliucci & Maarten Boudry (eds.), Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem, University of Chicago Press. pp. 247. 2013.
    This chapter examines arguments for the view that any science of the supernatural must be a pseudoscience. It shows that many of these arguments are not good arguments. It also argues that, contrary to recent philosophical discussions, the appeal to the supernatural should not be ruled out as science for methodological reasons, but rather because the notion of supernatural intervention probably suffers from fatal flaws.
  •  32
    The Case for Humanism: An Introduction
    with Lewis Vaughn and Austin Dacey
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 2003.
    The Case for Humanism is the premier textbook to introduce and help students think critically about the 'big ideas' of Western humanism—secularism, rationalism, materialism, science, democracy, individualism, and others—all powerful themes that run through Western thought from the ancient Greeks and the Enlightenment to the present day
  •  47
    Darwin’s Doubt, Calvin’s Calvary
    In Michael Ruse (ed.), Philosophy After Darwin: Classic and Contemporary Readings, Princeton University Press. pp. 309-322. 2009.
  •  76
    The Road to Damascus
    Faith and Philosophy 22 (4): 442-459. 2005.
  •  17
    Causes and Coincidences (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 465-468. 1995.
  •  19
    Successful Defense? (review)
    Philosophia Christi 3 (1): 7-35. 2001.
  •  47
    How to Be a Metaphysical Realist
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 253-274. 1988.
  •  187
    Plantinga's case against naturalistic epistemology
    Philosophy of Science 63 (3): 432-451. 1996.
    In Warrant and Proper Function, Alvin Plantinga claims that metaphysical naturalism, when joined to a naturalized epistemology, is self-undermining. Plantinga argues that naturalists are committed to a neoDarwinian account of our origins, and that the reliability of our cognitive faculties is improbable or unknown relative to that theory. If the theory is true, then we are in no position to know that, whereas theism, if true, underwrites cognitive reliability. I seek to turn the tables on Planti…Read more
  •  72
    World without design: The ontological consequences of naturalism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2): 494-497. 2005.
  •  75
    Davidson's compatibilism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 (December): 227-246. 1984.
  •  85
    Should God Not Have Created Adam?
    Faith and Philosophy 9 (2): 193-209. 1992.
  •  179
    This critical study of the third book of Plantinga's trilogy on proper-function epistemology begins by denying that classical foundationalism proposes a deontic conception of justification. Nor is it subject to Gettier counterexamples, as, I show, Plantinga's fallibilism is and must be. Plantinga's central thesis is that there's no way of attacking the rationality of central Christian beliefs without attacking their truth. That, I argue, is not so on several grounds, e.g., because one can demand…Read more
  •  43
    It has become something of a leitmotif among evangelical apologetes to argue that morality can have no objective foundation if there is no God. Using a strategy that appeals to many people's strong intuitions that there are objective rights and wrongs, they claim seek to convict atheists of being intellectually committed to moral relativism, subjectivism, or nihilism. Those are, of course, ethical positions that have been advocated by some atheists. But others share the intuition that there are …Read more
  •  34
    Opacity in the Attitudes
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (4). 1978.
    Philosophical logic has its problem-children; and among these the Principle of Substitutivity of codesignating expressions — the linguistic spawn of Leibniz's law—has achieved a place of prominence. It has become increasingly apparent that a certain style of linguistic analysis, which seeks to impose formal regimentation ruled by the constraints of classical quantification theory, does not yield results with the kind of uniformity and elegance one should hope for from a satisfyi.ng theory. The r…Read more
  •  28
    This study is a new look at the question of how God can act upon the world, and whether the world can affect God, examining contemporary work on the metaphysics of causation and laws of nature, and current work in the theory of knowledge and mysticism. It has been traditional to address such questions by appealing to God’s omnipotence and omniscience, but this book claims that this is useless unless it can be shown how these two powers "work." Instead of treating the familiar problems associated…Read more
  •  60
    Theoretical simplicity and defeasibility
    Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 273-288. 1978.
    Theoretical simplicity is difficult to characterize, and evidently can depend upon a number of distinct factors. One such desirable characteristic is that the laws of a theory have relatively few "counterinstances" whose accommodation requires the invocation of a ceteris paribus condition and ancillary explanation. It is argued that, when one theory is reduced to another, such that the laws of the second govern the behavior of the parts of the entities in the domain of the first, there is a char…Read more
  •  19
    "Causation: A Realist Approach" by Michael Tooley (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 605. 1990.