•  331
    Vision, knowledge, and assertion
    Consciousness and Cognition 41 41-49. 2016.
    I report two experiments studying the relationship among explicit judgments about what people see, know, and should assert. When an object of interest was surrounded by visibly similar items, it diminished people’s willingness to judge that an agent sees, knows, and should tell others that it is present. This supports the claim, made by many philosophers, that inhabiting a misleading environment intuitively decreases our willingness to attribute perception and knowledge. However, contrary to str…Read more
  •  331
    Selfless assertions: some empirical evidence
    Synthese 192 (4): 1221-1233. 2015.
    It is increasingly recognized that knowledge is the norm of assertion. As this view has gained popularity, it has also garnered criticism. One widely discussed criticism involves thought experiments about “selfless assertion.” Selfless assertions are said to be intuitively compelling examples where agents should assert propositions that they don’t even believe and, hence, don’t know. This result is then taken to show that knowledge is not the norm of assertion. This paper reports four experiment…Read more
  •  329
    Perceptions of Philosophical Inquiry: a Survey
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7 (4): 805-816. 2016.
    Six hundred three people completed a survey measuring perceptions of traditional areas of philosophical inquiry and their relationship to empirical science. The ten areas studied were: aesthetics, epistemology, ethics, history of philosophy, logic, metaphysics, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, and political philosophy. For each area, participants rated whether it is currently central to philosophy, whether its centrality depends on integration with science, and …Read more
  •  328
    Lying, fast and slow
    with Angelo Turri
    Synthese 198 (1): 757-775. 2019.
    Researchers have debated whether there is a relationship between a statement’s truth-value and whether it counts as a lie. One view is that a statement being objectively false is essential to whether it counts as a lie; the opposing view is that a statement’s objective truth-value is inessential to whether it counts as a lie. We report five behavioral experiments that use a novel range of behavioral measures to address this issue. In each case, we found evidence of a relationship. A statement’s …Read more
  •  327
    Knowledge and suberogatory assertion
    Philosophical Studies 167 (3): 557-567. 2014.
    I accomplish two things in this paper. First I expose some important limitations of the contemporary literature on the norms of assertion and in the process illuminate a host of new directions and forms that an account of assertional norms might take. Second I leverage those insights to suggest a new account of the relationship between knowledge and assertion, which arguably outperforms the standard knowledge account.
  •  327
    Excuse Validation: A Cross‐cultural Study
    Cognitive Science 43 (8). 2019.
    If someone unintentionally breaks the rules, do they break the rules? In the abstract, the answer is obviously “yes.” But, surprisingly, when considering specific examples of unintentional, blameless rule-breaking, approximately half of people judge that no rule was broken. This effect, known as excuse validation, has previously been observed in American adults. Outstanding questions concern what causes excuse validation, and whether it is peculiar to American moral psychology or cross-culturall…Read more
  •  317
    Promises to Keep: Speech Acts and the Value of Reflective Knowledge
    Logos and Episteme 2 (4): 583-590. 2011.
    This paper offers a new account of reflective knowledge’s value, building on recent work on the epistemic norms of speech acts. Reflective knowledge is valuable because it licenses us to make guarantees and promises.
  •  307
    Thomas Reid
    In Margaret Cameron, Benjamin Hill & Robert Stainton (eds.), Sourcebook in history of philosophy of language, Springer. pp. 807-809. 2016.
    A brief introduction to Thomas Reid's philosophy on language.
  •  307
    Knowledge and Skepticism (review)
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 1 (2): 155-157. 2011.
    A review of the collection "Knowledge and Skepticism" edited by Joseph Campbell, Michael O'Rourke, and Harry Silverstein.
  •  305
    Appeals to ordinary thought and talk are frequent in philosophy, perhaps nowhere more than in contemporary epistemology. When an epistemological theory implies serious error in “commonsense” or “folk” epistemology, it is counted as a cost of the view. Similarly, when an epistemological theory respects or vindicates deep patterns in commonsense epistemology, it is viewed as a benefit of the view. Philosophers typically rely on introspection and anecdotal social observation to support their charac…Read more
  •  301
    Prompting challenges
    Analysis 70 (3): 456-462. 2010.
    I consider a serious objection to the knowledge account of assertion and develop a response. In the process I introduce important new data on prompting assertion, which all theorists working in the area should take note of.
  •  299
    You can't get away with murder that easily: A response to Timothy Mulgan
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 13 (4). 2005.
    I respond to an objection against satisficing consequentialism, due to Tim Mulgan.
  •  295
    Deciding without Intending
    with Alexandra M. Nolte, Wesley Buckwalter, and David Rose
    Journal of Cognition 3 (1): 12. 2020.
    According to a consensus view in philosophy, “deciding” and “intending” are synonymous expressions. Researchers have recently challenged this view with the discovery of a counterexample in which ordinary speakers attribute deciding without intending. The aim of this paper is to investigate the strengths and limits of this discovery. The result of this investigation revealed that the evidence challenging the consensus view is strong. We replicate the initial finding against consensus and extend i…Read more
  •  282
    Knowledge and Assertion in Korean
    with YeounJun Park
    Cognitive Science 42 (6): 2060-2080. 2018.
    Evidence from life science, cognitive science, and philosophy supports the hypothesis that knowledge is a central norm of the human practice of assertion. However, to date, the experimental evidence supporting this hypothesis is limited to American anglophones. If the hypothesis is correct, then such findings will not be limited to one language or culture. Instead, we should find a strong connection between knowledge and assertability across human languages and cultures. To begin testing this pr…Read more
  •  280
    Assertion and Assurance: Some Empirical Evidence
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (1): 214-222. 2015.
    I report three experiments relevant to evaluating Krista Lawlor's theory of assurance, respond to her criticism of the knowledge account of assertion, and propose an alternative theory of assurance.
  •  269
    Stumbling in Nozick’s Tracks
    Logos and Episteme 3 (2): 291-293. 2012.
    Rachael Briggs and Daniel Nolan have recently proposed an improved version of Nozick’s tracking account of knowledge. I show that, despite its virtues, the new proposal suffers from three serious problems.
  •  266
    Ernest Sosa
    In Robert Audi (ed.), Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 3rd Edition, Cambridge University Press. 2015.
    A lexicographical entry on "Ernest Sosa".
  •  265
    Linguistic intuitions in context: a defense of nonskeptical pure invariantism.
    In Anthony Booth & Darrell P. Rowbottom (eds.), Intuitions, Oxford University Press. pp. 165-184. 2014.
    Epistemic invariantism is the view that the truth conditions of knowledge ascriptions don’t vary across contexts. Epistemic purism is the view that purely practical factors can’t directly affect the strength of your epistemic position. The combination of purism and invariantism, pure invariantism, is the received view in contemporary epistemology. It has lately been criticized by contextualists, who deny invariantism, and impurists, who deny purism. A central charge against pure invariantism is …Read more
  •  261
    Review of Robert C. Roberts and W. Jay Wood, Intellectual Virtues (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (3). 2011.
    A review of "Intellectual virtues: an essay in regulative epistemology" by Robert Roberts and Jay Wood.
  •  261
    Irksome assertions
    Philosophical Studies 166 (1): 123-128. 2013.
    The Knowledge Account of Assertion (KAA) says that knowledge is the norm of assertion: you may assert a proposition only if you know that it’s true. The primary support for KAA is an explanatory inference from a broad range of linguistic data. The more data that KAA well explains, the stronger the case for it, and the more difficult it is for the competition to keep pace. In this paper we critically assess a purported new linguistic datum, which, it has been argued, KAA well explains. We argue t…Read more
  •  249
    The distinctive “should” of assertability
    Philosophical Psychology 30 (4): 481-489. 2017.
    Recent work has assumed that the normativity associated with assertion differs from the normativity of morality, practical rationality, etiquette, and legality. That is, whether an assertion “should” be made is not merely a function of these other familiar sorts of normativity and is especially connected to truth. Some researchers have challenged this assumption of distinctive normativity. In this paper I report two experiments that test the assumption. Participants read a brief story, judged wh…Read more
  •  246
    That's Outrageous
    Theoria 79 (2): 167-171. 2013.
    I show how non-presentists ought to respond to a popular objection originally due to Arthur Prior and lately updated by Dean Zimmerman. Prior and Zimmerman say that non-presentism cannot account for the fittingness of certain emotional responses to things past. But presentism gains no advantage here, because it is equally incapable of accounting for the fittingness of certain other emotional responses to things past, in particular moral outrage.
  •  218
    Mythology of the Factive
    Logos and Episteme 2 (1): 141-150. 2011.
    It’s a cornerstone of epistemology that knowledge requires truth – that is, that knowledge is factive. Allan Hazlett boldly challenges orthodoxy by arguing thatthe ordinary concept of knowledge is not factive. On this basis Hazlett further argues that epistemologists shouldn’t concern themselves with the ordinary concept of knowledge, or knowledge ascriptions and related linguistic phenomena. I argue that either Hazlett is wrong about the ordinary concept of knowledge, or he’s right in a way tha…Read more
  •  217
    Creative reasoning
    In John Turri & Peter D. Klein (eds.), Ad infinitum: new essays on epistemological infinitism, Oxford University Press. pp. 210-226. 2014.
    I defend the unpopular view that inference can create justification. I call this view inferential creationism. Inferential creationism has been favored by infinitists, who think that it supports infinitism. But it doesn’t. Finitists can and should accept creationism.
  •  209
    Iffy predictions and proper expectations
    Synthese 191 (8): 1857-1866. 2014.
    What individuates the speech act of prediction? The standard view is that prediction is individuated by the fact that it is the unique speech act that requires future-directed content. We argue against this view and two successor views. We then lay out several other potential strategies for individuating prediction, including the sort of view we favor. We suggest that prediction is individuated normatively and has a special connection to the epistemic standards of expectation. In the process, we…Read more
  •  208
    The epistemic closure principle says that knowledge is closed under known entailment. The closure principle is deeply implicated in numerous core debates in contemporary epistemology. Closure’s opponents claim that there are good theoretical reasons to abandon it. Closure’s proponents claim that it is a defining feature of ordinary thought and talk and, thus, abandoning it is radically revisionary. But evidence for these claims about ordinary practice has thus far been anecdotal. In this paper, …Read more
  •  206
    Knowledge and suberogatory assertion
    Philosophical Studies (3): 1-11. 2013.
    I accomplish two things in this paper. First I expose some important limitations of the contemporary literature on the norms of assertion and in the process illuminate a host of new directions and forms that an account of assertional norms might take. Second I leverage those insights to suggest a new account of the relationship between knowledge and assertion, which arguably outperforms the standard knowledge account.
  •  183
    Refutation by elimination
    Analysis 70 (1): 35-39. 2010.
    This paper refutes two important and influential views in one fell stroke. The first is G.E. Moore’s view that assertions of the form ‘Q but I don’t believe that Q’ are inherently “absurd.” The second is Gareth Evans’s view that justification to assert Q entails justification to assert that you believe Q. Both views run aground the possibility of being justified in accepting eliminativism about belief. A corollary is that a principle recently defended by John Williams is also false, namely, that…Read more
  •  182
    You gotta believe
    In Clayton Littlejohn & John Turri (eds.), Epistemic norms: new essays on action, belief and assertion, Oxford University Press. pp. 193-199. 2014.
    Proper assertion requires belief. In support of this thesis, I provide an explanatory argument from linguistic patterns surrounding assertion and show how to handle cases of "selfless" assertion.