Alan Wertheimer
(1942 - 2015)

  •  70
    No Exceptionalism Needed to Treat Terrorists
    with Chiara Lepora and Marion Danis
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (10): 53-54. 2009.
    Gesundheit and colleagues offer dramatic examples of the medical treatment of terrorists but then pose the suggestion that those who engage in terrorism forfeit their right to medical care, and, consequently, that physicians have no obligation to treat them. Their argument presupposes that a physician’s obligation to provide medical care depends on the patients’ right to health care. Therefore, someone who commits heinous and abhorrent acts thereby waives the right to health care and the phy…Read more
  •  5
    Thirteen. Coercive proposals: II
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 222-241. 1990.
  •  19
    Sixteen. Coercion and voluntariness
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 287-306. 1990.
  •  2
    Contents
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. 1990.
  •  11
    Preface
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. 1990.
  •  7
    Books in Review
    Political Theory 18 (1): 180-184. 1990.
  •  71
    Voluntary Consent: Why a Value-Neutral Concept Won't Work
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (3): 226-254. 2012.
    Some maintain that voluntariness is a value-neutral concept. On that view, someone acts involuntarily if subject to a controlling influence or has no acceptable alternatives. I argue that a value-neutral conception of voluntariness cannot explain when and why consent is invalid and that we need a moralized account of voluntariness. On that view, most concerns about the voluntariness of consent to participate in research are not well founded
  •  42
    Reevaluating the Right to Withdraw From Research Without Penalty
    American Journal of Bioethics 11 (4): 14-16. 2011.
    In “Assessing the Remedy: The Case for Contracts in Clinical Trials,” Sarah Edwards (2011) proposes that research participants acquire contractual obligations to investigators, thus opening the doo...
  •  11
    Fifteen. From coercive proposals to coercion
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 267-286. 1990.
  •  64
    When and Why Is Research without Consent Permissible?
    Hastings Center Report 46 (2): 35-43. 2016.
    The view that research with competent adults requires valid consent to be ethical perhaps finds its clearest expression in the Nuremberg Code, whose famous first principle asserts that “the voluntary consent of the human subject is absolutely essential.” In a similar vein, the United Nations International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights states that “no one shall be subjected without his free consent to medical or scientific experimentation.” Yet although some formulations of the consent p…Read more
  •  83
    There are (STILL) no coercive offers
    Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9): 592-593. 2014.
    John McMillan's article raises numerous important points about the ethics of surgical castration of sex offenders.1 In this commentary, we focus solely on and argue against the claim that the offer of release from detention conditional upon surgical castration is a coercive offer that compromises the validity of the offender's consent. We take no view on the question as to whether castration for sex offenders is ethically permissible. But, we reject the claim that it is ethically permissible onl…Read more
  •  48
    Deterrence and retribution
    Ethics 86 (3): 181-199. 1976.
  •  53
    Introduction -- Facing up to paternalism in research ethics -- Preface to a theory of consent transactions in research : beyond valid consent -- Should we worry about money? -- Exploitation in clinical research -- The interaction principle.
  •  4
    Books in Review
    Political Theory 10 (1): 137-140. 1982.
  •  11
    Nine. Coercion and the law: Conclusion
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 170-176. 1990.
  •  5
    Acknowledgments
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. 1990.
  •  2
    Index
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 311-319. 1990.
  •  6
    Ten. The language of coercion
    In Coercion, Princeton University Press. pp. 179-191. 1990.
  •  115
    Facing up to paternalism in research ethics
    Hastings Center Report 37 (3): 24-34. 2007.
    : Bioethicists have failed to understand the pervasively paternalistic character of research ethics. Not only is the overall structure of research review and regulation paternalistic in some sense; even the way informed consent is sought may imply paternalism. Paternalism has limits, however. Getting clear on the paternalism of research ethics may mean some kinds of prohibited research should be reassessed
  •  96
    Exploitation in clinical research
    In Ezekiel J. Emanuel (ed.), The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 201--10. 2008.
  •  70
    Should 'nudge' be salvaged?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (8): 498-499. 2013.
    Policy makers are understandably interested—for both political and moral reasons—in following Thaler and Sunstein's recommendation to use ‘choice architecture’ , or other ‘nudges’, to promote desirable behaviour in ways that are allegedly compatible with personal freedom.1 Yashar Saghai's intricate analysis shows that simply maintaining the target's choice-set is insufficient to preserve the target's freedom when the nudge bypasses the target's deliberative capacities—as it is specifically desig…Read more
  •  305
    Consent and Sexual Relations
    Legal Theory 2 (2): 89-112. 1996.
    This article has two broad purposes. First, as a political philosopher who has been interested in the concepts of coercion and exploitation, I want to consider just what the analysis of the concept of consent can bring to the question, what sexually motivated behavior should be prohibited through the criminal law? Put simply, I shall argue that conceptual analysis will be of little help. Second, and with somewhat fewer professional credentials, I shall offer some thoughts about the substantive q…Read more
  •  79
    Payment for research participation: a coercive offer?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (5): 389-392. 2008.
    Payment for research participation has raised ethical concerns, especially with respect to its potential for coercion. We argue that characterising payment for research participation as coercive is misguided, because offers of benefit cannot constitute coercion. In this article we analyse the concept of coercion, refute mistaken conceptions of coercion and explain why the offer of payment for research participation is never coercive but in some cases may produce undue inducement
  •  7
    Books in Review
    Political Theory 17 (2): 330-333. 1989.
  •  39
    Is payment a benefit?
    Bioethics 27 (2): 105-116. 2011.
    What I call ‘the standard view’ claims that IRBs should not regard financial payment as a benefit to subjects for the purpose of risk/benefit assessment. Although the standard view is universally accepted, there is little defense of that view in the canonical documents of research ethics or the scholarly literature. This paper claims that insofar as IRBs should be concerned with the interests and autonomy of research subjects, they should reject the standard view and adopt ‘the incorporation vie…Read more
  •  69
    Why Adopt a Maximin Theory of Exploitation?
    American Journal of Bioethics 10 (6): 38-39. 2010.
    Angela Ballantyne (2010) argues that international research is exploitative when the transactions between researchers and participants who lack basic goods do not provide participants with the maxi...