Julia Driver

University of Texas at Austin
University of St. Andrews
Johns Hopkins University
Department of Philosophy
PhD
Austin, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Value Theory
Meta-Ethics
Normative Ethics
Areas of Interest
Value Theory
  •  169
    Response to my critics
    Utilitas 16 (1): 33-41. 2004.
    This essay is a rejoinder to comments on Uneasy Virtue made by Onora O'Neill, John Skorupski, and Michael Slote in this issue. In Uneasy Virtue I presented criticisms of traditional virtue theory. I also presented an alternative – a consequentialist account of virtue, one which is a form of ‘pure evaluational externalism’. This type of theory holds that the moral quality of character traits is determined by factors external to agency (e.g. consequences). All three commentators took exception to …Read more
  •  69
    Book review: Morals from motives by Michael Slote (review)
    The Journal of Ethics 7 (2): 233-237. 2003.
  •  148
    On virtue ethics
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 122-127. 2002.
    Rosalind Hursthouse has written an excellent book, in which she develops a neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics that she sees as avoiding some of the major criticisms leveled against virtue ethics in general, and against Aristotle's brand of virtue ethics in particular.
  •  18
    Love and Duty
    Philosophic Exchange 44 (1). 2014.
    The thesis of this paper is that there is an important asymmetry between a duty to love and a duty to not love: there is no duty to love as a fitting response to someone’s very good qualities, but there is a duty to not love as a fitting response to someone’s very bad qualities. The source of the asymmetry that I discuss is the two-part understanding of love: the emotional part and the evaluative commitment part. One cannot directly, or “at will,” control an emotional response, but one can under…Read more
  •  68
    The Virtues of Ignorance
    Journal of Philosophy 86 (7): 373. 1989.
  •  36
    How Are We to Live? (review)
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 125-126. 1997.
    Peter Singer is well known as an ethicist who has contributed much to current debates in ethics and public policy. He has published on topics ranging from vegetarianism to famine relief to bioethics, always with something interesting to say, and often with something provocative as well. How Are We to Live? adds to Singer’s work in the area of applied, or practical, ethics. This book is not as deeply challenging as some of Singer’s earlier work. However, it is not intended for an audience compose…Read more
  •  342
    The history of utilitarianism
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010.
  •  91
    Consequentialism and Feminist Ethics
    Hypatia 20 (4): 183-199. 2005.
    This essay attempts to show that sophisticated consequentialism is able to accommodate the concerns that have traditionally been raised by feminist writers in ethics. Those concerns have primarily to do with the fact that consequentialism is seen as both too demanding of the individual and neglectful of the agent's special obligations to family and friends. Here, I argue that instrumental justification for partiality can be provided, for example, even though an attitude of partiality is not char…Read more
  •  354
    Autonomy and the Asymmetry Problem for Moral Expertise
    Philosophical Studies 128 (3): 619-644. 2006.
    We seem less likely to endorse moral expertise than reasoning expertise or aesthetic expertise. This seems puzzling given that moral norms are intuitively taken to be at least more objective than aesthetic norms. One possible diagnosis of the asymmetry is that moral judgments require autonomy of judgement in away that other judgments do not. However, the author points out that aesthetic judgments that have been ‘borrowed’ by aesthetic experts generate the same autonomy worry as moral judgments w…Read more
  •  307
    Moral expertise: Judgment, practice, and analysis*: Julia driver
    Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2): 280-296. 2013.
    This essay defends moral expertise against the skeptical considerations raised by Gilbert Ryle and others. The core of the essay articulates an account of moral expertise that draws on work on expertise in empirical moral psychology, and develops an analogy between moral expertise and linguistic expertise. The account holds that expertise is contrastive, so that a person is an expert relative to a particular contrast. Further, expertise is domain specific and characterized by “automatic” behavio…Read more
  •  118
    Humble arrogance
    Metaphilosophy 38 (4): 365-369. 2007.
    This essay defends consequentialist approaches to moral evaluation from a charge of moral arrogance made by Bernard Gert in “Moral Arrogance and Moral Theories.” A distinction is made between a commitment to there being a right answer to moral questions and certainty about the nature of the right answers.
  •  251
    Imaginative resistance and psychological necessity
    Social Philosophy and Policy 25 (1): 301-313. 2008.
    Some of our moral commitments strike us as necessary, and this feature of moral phenomenology is sometimes viewed as incompatible with sentimentalism, since sentimentalism holds that our commitments depend, in some way, on sentiment. His dependence, or contingency, is what seems incompatible with necessity. In response to this sentimentalists hold that the commitments are psychologically necessary. However, little has been done to explore this kind of necessity. In this essay I discuss psycholog…Read more
  •  525
    The suberogatory
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3). 1992.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  84
    Caesar's wife: On the moral significance of appearing good
    Journal of Philosophy 89 (7): 331-343. 1992.
  •  121
    Consequentialism
    Routledge. 2012.
    Consequentialism is the view that the rightness or wrongness of actions depend solely on their consequences. It is one of the most influential, and controversial, of all ethical theories. In this book, Julia Driver introduces and critically assesses consequentialism in all its forms. After a brief historical introduction to the problem, Driver examines utilitarianism, and the arguments of its most famous exponents, John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham, and explains the fundamental questions under…Read more
  •  89
    Private Blame
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2): 215-220. 2016.
    This paper explores a problem for Michael McKenna’s conversation model of moral responsibility that views blame as characteristically part of a conversational exchange. The problem for this model on which this paper focuses is the problem of private blame. Sometimes when we blame we do so without any intention to engage in a communicative exchange. It is argued that McKenna’s model cannot adequately account for private blame.
  •  2
    Luck and Fortune in Moral Evaluation
    In Martijn Blaauw (ed.), Contrastivism in philosophy, Routledge/taylor & Francis Group. 2013.
  •  163
    The Conflation of Moral and Epistemic Virtue
    Metaphilosophy 34 (3): 367-383. 2003.
    Accounts of virtue suffer a conflation problem when they appear unable to preserve intuitive distinctions between types of virtue. In this essay I argue that a number of influential attempts to preserve the distinction between moral and epistemic virtues fail, on the grounds that they characterize virtuous traits in terms of ‘characteristic motivation’. I claim that this does not distinguish virtuous traits at the level of value‐conferring quality, and I propose that the best alternative is to d…Read more
  •  308
    Uneasy Virtue
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    The predominant view of moral virtue can be traced back to Aristotle. He believed that moral virtue must involve intellectual excellence. To have moral virtue one must have practical wisdom - the ability to deliberate well and to see what is morally relevant in a given context. Julia Driver challenges this classical theory of virtue, arguing that it fails to take into account virtues which do seem to involve ignorance or epistemic defect. Some 'virtues of ignorance' are counterexamples to accoun…Read more
  •  82
    Hyperactive ethics
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174): 9-25. 1994.
  •  10
    The Practice of Moral Judgment
    Philosophical Books 35 (2): 106-108. 1994.
  •  67
    Consequentialism and Feminist Ethics
    Hypatia 20 (4): 183-199. 2000.
    This essay attempts to show that sophisticated consequentialism is able to accommodate the concerns that have traditionally been raised by feminist writers in ethics. Those concerns have primarily to do with the fact that consequentialism is seen as both too demanding of the individual and neglectful of the agent's special obligations to family and friends. Here, I argue that instrumental justification for partiality can be provided, for example, even though an attitude of partiality is not char…Read more
  •  33
    Review of Brad Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (6). 2002.
  •  44
    An Introduction to Kant'S Ethics
    Philosophical Books 37 (4): 258-260. 1996.
  •  97
    Moral sense and sentimentalism
    In Roger Crisp (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 358. 2013.
    This chapter focuses on sentimentalism – the view that morality is based on sentiment – in particular, the sentiment of sympathy. Sentimentalism was historically articulated in opposition to two positions: Hobbesian egoism, in which morality is based on self-interest; and Moral Rationalism, which held that morality is based on reason alone. The Sentimentalists challenged both views, arguing that there is more to what motivates human beings than simple self-interest and that reason alone is insuf…Read more
  •  52
    Introduction
    Utilitas 13 (2): 137. 2001.
    The evaluation of character has taken on new significance in moral theory, and, indeed, some advocate a shift in focus away from evaluating action to evaluating character. This has been taken to pose special challenges for utilitarian and consequentialist moral theory. Utilitarianism's commitment to impartiality and its seeming failure to accommodate virtue evaluation have led to problems, some of which are developed in the essays in this volume
  •  13
    Knowing Better by Daniel Star
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3): 713-719. 2016.